Tumgik
#the threefold narrative of the statement itself
ivisionsmart-blog · 5 years
Text
Help writing a paper with Paper Samples
A judgment may consist of one subject and one predicate, or of several subjects and predicates. According to the composition of the subject and predicate judgments are divided into simple and complex. A simple judgment is a judgment consisting of one subject and one predicate. A complex judgment is one in which there are several predicates or subjects. Complex judgments consist of a few simple judgments. Judgments and suggestions Every proposition is always grammatically expressed in the form of a sentence. A proposition cannot exist outside of a proposition. The proposition is the immediate reality of the judgment, its material envelope. However, not every sentence expresses a judgment - help writing a paper .
The characteristic features of judgment are the affirmation or denial of anything about anything. Therefore, if something is affirmed or denied in a sentence, it expresses a judgment; if there is no affirmation or negation in the sentence, then the sentence is not a judgment. The proposal, as we know, there are declarative, interrogative and incentive. In rozpovidnih proposals, for example, "the Court is a body of justice"; "the Expert is not a witness" and the like necessarily available or statement or denial, so any rozpovidne proposal is a judgment. This does not mean, of course, that the difference between proposition and proposition disappears in such cases; it remains. Judgment is a logical category, sentence is a grammatical category. A judgment is always threefold: it has a subject, a predicate, and connections. The sentence is not always three-membered: it can be one-membered ("light"; "frost", etc.), and two-membered ("rain comes", "the World will win", etc.). and polynomial ("Kiev is the most beautiful city in Ukraine" , etc.). In addition to the subject and predicate, grammatically a sentence has minor terms: definition, addition, circumstance - https://www.livepaperhelp.com/paper-for-money.html .
The logical structure of judgments is international. In its main features, it is common to a variety of peoples. The structure of the sentence, on the contrary, is largely national, it is determined by the set of grammatical features characteristic of a given language, which distinguishes it from other languages. Thus the question of the relation of proposition and proposition is decided when we consider judgments and narrative proposition.
The purpose of interrogative and propositional sentences is different from affirmation or negation. The essence of the interrogative sentence is to pose the question, and the incentive sentence is to Express the motivation. When we ask the question: "is Petrenko an accomplice?", then in the question itself there is no statement or denial, we do not claim that Petrenko is an accomplice, and do not deny it, that is, do not Express any definite judgment about Petrenko. What the question is aimed at is not yet known to us. So, when we ask the question, for example: "Where were you yesterday at 10pm?"Who gave you this thing?"; "Where was the victim?"; "Who owns this axe?"etc., we do not yet Express judgments. A judgment, that is, a thought in which something is affirmed or denied, will only be the answer to a question, viz. : "Yesterday at 10 o'clock in the evening I was in cinema"; "Petrenko gave me this thing"; "the Victim stood near a window of the house"; "this axe belongs to Nikolaev", etc.
0 notes
trinitiesblog · 7 years
Text
Kimel’s review of What is the Trinity – Part 4
I’m having a hard time keeping up with his blogging! His long part 4 of his review of What is the Trinity? is here: “Trinity, Creation, and the Christian Distinction.” He starts by noticing this famous “triadic” text from Paul:
“The grace of the Lord Jesus Christ and the love of God and the fellowship of the Holy Spirit be with you all” (2 Cor 13:14).
But he doesn’t notice, as a great scholar has pointed out, that this not what a trinitarian should expect! The three are in the wrong order, and the Father, not the three of them together, is called “God”! But it is what a unitarian would expect.
He continues to weave his story about how even the earliest Christianity was “trinitarian.”
Before there was a doctrine of the Holy Trinity, there simply was the Holy Trinity in whose reality Christians lived and prayed. The Trinitarian naming structured and formed the worship of the Church. From the beginning believers prayed to the Father, through and with the Son, in and by the Spirit.
Again, it doesn’t register with him that this is a unitarian friendly pattern of prayer, and not what one would expect from trinitarians! As I mentioned last time, he’s just happy to have found something triple/threefold early on – even if it’s not a conception of the one God. But that’s not the same as finding trinitarian theology to be presupposed! These folks are all explicitly confessing belief in one God [aka] the Father Almighty, the creator.
When confronted with the charge of polytheism, they no doubt insisted that they worshipped and served the one God of Israel, yet to this one God they now attached, by divine revelation and sacramental mandate, the names of Jesus and the Spirit, as exemplified in the earliest examples of credal faith.
This is demonstrably wrong; read the apologists of the 100s and 200s, and see how they actually reply to the charge of polytheism. I’m starting to lose my patience with these “just so” stories, which people find it so convenient to imagine. We need to anchor any true narrative about early Christianity in the actual evidence. Fr. Kimel seems to appeal to the authority of the late theologian Jenson here, but that doesn’t seem to the point. After the quote:
Hence we may speak of a foundational Trinitarianism embodied in the stories, hymns, and ritual practices of the apostolic Church.
We may so speak, if we want to mislead people into to thinking that early Christians believed in a triune God, rather than merely in the triad of God, his Son, and his Spirit or spirit. I should not mince words here; this statement is an abuse of words. We ought to reserve “trinitarianism” for things having to do with the triune God of catholic orthodoxy.
He then rehearses the idea of creation from nothing, which pagan philosophers thought to be incoherent.  He supposes that, somehow,
The sense of divine transcendence made possible by the creatio ex nihilo opens up the possibility of thinking the mystery of three equally divine hypostases united in perichoretic union
I don’t get it. I don’t see any connection. But his idea seems to be that intuitions about impossibility should be confined to the realm of natural things, so that we should think that there can be no objection to the idea of a tripersonal god. This seems to misunderstand the very idea of metaphysical possibility, though.
But his point is that seeming incoherence is to be expected in theology:
The articulation of the mysteries of Incarnation and Trinity requires us to employ the language of paradox and antinomy, but that is what one should expect, if God is radically transcendent in the way the catholic tradition affirms.
That seems an obvious non sequitur to me, for the reasons I’ve explained here. I think this at bottom amounts to the fallacy of special pleading. For my theory, seeming incoherence is a good thing. Of course, such would sink just about any other theory. I think the sense of being in a dominant majority prevents Christians like Fr. Kimel from seeing this as the problem it is. If this is just part of Tradition, how could it be arbitrary?
He then rehearses the idea that God is “Being Itself.” I think this is utterly wrongheaded philosophy – atheistic in fact, as it makes the ultimate reality to be a something-or-other which is not a god. But in any case, his point is just that divine transcendence should make us friendly to seeming theological incoherence. I’ve already said that I don’t think that follows. And let me also say that this claim is not at all part of any OT or NT teaching. We ought to wonder if we can get along without this help from Platonic philosophy. We should be afraid lest we build our house on philosophical sand, and not on Jesus’s theology and that of his apostles.
Is it possible for the analytic philosophical tradition to think beyond its logic and apprehend the radical distinction between Deity and cosmos? If it does not, it will never grasp the holy mysteries of the Christian faith.
Well, it’s no harder than grasping the distinction between an apparent contradiction and a real one, and discussing divine transcendence, and ineffability, and whether terms can apply univocally to both God and to creatures – things many analytic philosophers do. Indeed, some, like Brian Davies, Ed Feser, and William Vallicella, endorse the “Being Itself” conception of the ultimate.
The real question, I think, is whether or not this idea about “God” is consistent with biblical teaching. Is YHWH supposed to be the greatest of the gods, and so, a god, or is “he” rather on inconceivable Something? Is he like a Father, or is It like a blinding light or an impenetrable darkness?
http://trinities.org/blog/kimels-review-of-what-is-the-trinity-part-4/
0 notes