Tumgik
#contributes nothing to society to a majority perspective (if that exists) deserves no less than someone who does
suncaptor · 4 years
Text
everyone should be allowed to do anything they want as long as they aren't causing unwanted harm/infringing the freedom of another person, but also people are good and everyone SHOULD help and provide for one another in whatever means they have necessary since the average human wants to help and contribute to society in some way and without the restraints of systems benefitting the worst traits in humanity, they would have the opportunity to do so.
0 notes
teacherintransition · 3 years
Text
The Ugly American...who? Me?
Tumblr media
My wife an I have become avid travelers and the closing of countries due to Covid-19 has hit us in the heart...
The time at home has given me chance to read about travel and given me pause to re-evaluate my behavior while abroad in the past and for the future...
The Ugly American, a novel written in the late 1950’s and which was a The New York Times Best Seller, was written by political scientist Eugene Burdick and writer and former U.S. Navy captain William Lederer. The book took a much needed look at the behavior of Americans traveling abroad; from the rugged backpacker hiking India to the field State Department personnel actually presenting the “official face” of our country in the international community. Prior to World War 1, most international travel by Americans was done by the wealthy elite among society. The “common” man through the tribulations of war, was given the opportunity to experience European culture and a yearning for seeing the world was fostered. If fact, there was a saying after WWI, “how you gonna keep Johnny on the farm after he’s seen Paree (Paris)?” The travel bug... wanderlust was born in the hearts of the middle class and gave rise to this phenomenon in film and in books written by Jack Kerouac, Cheryl Strayed, Ernest Hemingway up to contemporary writers like Anthony Bourdain, Andrew Sean Greer and Elizabeth Gilbert. Even Rick Steves who has become a knowledgeable source of traveling information with his travel guide series, has presented an informative open minded view of travel abroad.
Tumblr media
All of these written treasures of traveling the world unveils to readers the magic that is to be found by stepping out your front door. The Ugly American presents a scathing look at how the “American” while overseas, displays an arrogant , intolerant, dismissive view of cultures far older and in many cases, more refined than ours. Burdick and Lederer’s book is set within the intrigues of international diplomacy and how that uniquely American view creates failure in the establishment of effective foreign policy. The authors listed and many more besides, instruct their readers to varying degrees to take more note of the intricate nuances a traveler should pay attention to and to show respect and admiration for the centuries of history and culture that exists all around us and that is not American. There is a common thread throughout all their works about what is missed when we stand outside and dismiss the uniqueness of every nation we might visit, instead of immersing oneself and appreciating it in a culture not our own. The “ugly American” has become a mythos of how Americans respond critically to anything that is not “MURICAN!”
Several other factors besides short sighted American foreign policy have contributed to the yoke placed on Americans traveling: cutthroat business practices while dealing with European, Asian and African countries; missionaries whose demonstrate a dismissive view of spiritual practices that have existed for millennia and, quite honestly, the behavior of tourists while abroad. Many experienced travelers draw a clear distinction between the tourist and the traveler. Kathryn Walsh differentiates the two in the following way:
Tourists
It's usually easy for locals to spot a tourist among them. A tourist may carry a camera, guidebook and map at all times and wear the same clothing he'd wear at home. Tourists tend to stay in their comfort zones a bit; they may speak only English instead of trying to learn phrases in the local language; stick to major cities instead of venturing to smaller towns or off-the-beaten-path locales; and stay in areas where the amenities are similar to what they have at home.
Travelers
Generally speaking, someone who considers himself a traveler will try to immerse himself in the local culture rather than standing out. If you're a traveler, you may try to explore the less-traveled areas and explore locations where tourism doesn't drive the economy. You'll interact with locals. Your goals for a trip will be to learn and experience new things, rather than to take a relaxing break from everyday life. A traveler may consider a trip a journey rather than a vacation.
The traveler presents a deferential, respectful and admiring view of the nations they are visiting and adopt the wise phrase from antiquity: “when in Rome do as the Romans.”
Tumblr media
There is nothing wrong with being a tourist, often it is the less expensive approach to travel, unless you become the arrogant American tourist then perhaps you need to reassess. Travel is a big part of my retirement plans and goals, but you know what they say about the best laid plans. Two highly anticipated trips with two years involved in planning were rescheduled due to the Covid-19 pandemic, a disappointment we shared with thousands of tourists and travelers alike; and further postponements may continue to confront us. Perspective is needed in such a situation as being denied travel is far below other struggles this event has presented all of us. That being said, it has been a terrible disappointment down to my bones. We’ve missed much needed fellowship time with great friends, the excitement of seeing new places, the immersion in the culture and history of the locales, and, for me personally, our yearly travels have been my muse and inspiration for so much of my art. It’s akin to being very thirsty and having only a few drops to suffice. Introspection is the course of action when hopefully contemplating the possibility of the trips occurring.
To satiate the urge, we’ve read and watched travel programs in the interim and have evaluated our connection to the Ugly American concept? Are we ...them? In our past travels, have we appeared at all dismissive of the people and practices of the places we’ve visited? My wife and I have always been in awe of our travel destinations, so I feel fairly confident that we have not displayed the aforementioned arrogance of many American travelers. The thought that then arises is how much we have not allowed ourselves to be immersed in the culture; which, in the long run, is a detriment to us more than anyone. Our minds are open and willing to become part of the places we visit, but if we eliminate the brusque nature of so many Americans while overseas, what is the stumbling block that draws such distinctions when traveling? I fully concede that most Americans feel they have little to learn from many places on this planet, more is the pity, and there is much flawed thinking that goes into this mindset; but what fundamental differences exist between the cultures? I came across a very enlightening blog article written by Alain Veilell that was spot on in identifying the differences. Veilell simply observed that we run on different clocks. Not literal clocks but a “clock” obsessed with structure and deadline.... hello Americans! Veilell notes that Europeans start late and end late, while American and many Asian cultures start early and end early. Americans tend to view the un-regimented approach as being akin to laziness. I coached soccer and baseball for many years and many of my Latino players would not be as punctual as my other players. They were as talented and competitive, but their homes weren’t ruled by the seconds on a clock. Dinner started later, lasted longer, the dishes could wait... the priority was the quality of interaction with the people your with... ah, there it is ... sort of.
Tumblr media
The average American meal last twenty minutes, while the average meal in Spain, for example, lasts two hours. They certainly don’t eat as much as Americans so why all the extra time? Why should time even be a factor so often? It’s the conversation and fellowship that is the priority not timing. While without question, the structured regimentation is a contributing factor to the American commitment to financial success, it also contributes to hypertension, stress, anxiety, depression and conflict that might be avoided with having an extra glass of wine and talking and not worrying if dinner is on schedule. Taking a little more time, enjoying the moment, letting serendipity reign may not be part and parcel of the Puritan work ethic; but it plays a helluva big part in realizing “La Dolce Vita.” This perception of time throws the rhythm off for many American tourists and makes us the ones to call the front desk complaining that the folks in room 210 are just too loud at 9:30 pm. The local population may just be getting ready to start dinner at that time. Remember, “when in Rome do as the Romans?”
While traveling, often American tourists view differences as a personal affront. “ I have to ask for ice?’ “What, no air conditioner?’ “They call the restroom the toilet?’ “Ugh how vulgar ... and a bidet? You must be kidding?” Truth to tell, Americans also suffer from mischaracterization from travelers from abroad as well. If I had a nickel for ever foreign exchange student who thought that all of Texas was a giant ranch with everyone riding horses and wearing cowboy hats. I think though that visitors to our country more often than not allow themselves to be pleasantly surprised than to have their feathers ruffled. It seems that we allow the “ours is better than yours” mentality to outweigh the magic of the unknown and the different. Every spiritual guiding ethos advocates living in the moment, treasure what is happening right now, greet the unknown with hope not hostility. The ugly American leaves no room for such an upbeat approach. Superiority mentality leave very little to treasure in this magnificent world other than what is yours and that limits learning, excitement, growth and just the pure joy that comes from trekking this world.
Is this assessment of mine a blanket judgement? No, not at all but there is some truth to it and there is something to be learned. As I self analyze, I found that I may harbor some of these traits and it’s good that I have time to stand back and look ...to learn. The worthy goal of being an affirming member of this global community is a purpose that I seek; and the rewards are far beyond just being intrinsic but rewards the cultures you visit with an admiration and respect they deserve. As these thoughts have been put down, it reignites the hopes that the planned journeys come to realization with the anticipation of more to follow. No more ugly Americans, British, Japanese or what have you, just eager travelers wanting to see and experience all that this world has to offer. Happy travels my friends.
Tumblr media
Burdick, Eugene Lederer, William; The Ugly American ; Norton Publications; 1958
Veilel, Alain; “Why don’t Europeans Travel to Cancun?;” Quora; October 8, 2020
Walsh, Kathryn. "Differences Between a Tourist and a Traveller" traveltips.usatoday.com, https://traveltips.usatoday.com/differences-between-tourist-traveller-103756.html. 5 April 2021.
Photo from https://www.myheritage.com/
Photo from https://openlibrary.org/authors/OL13640A/Ernest_Hemingway
5 notes · View notes
berniesrevolution · 6 years
Link
I detest the word “neoliberalism.” I mean, it really makes me cringe. I generally impose a strict rule that writers are not allowed to use it. (Though we do offer a coupon for one free use, and as the editor I cannot be prevented from printing as many coupons as I like.) I have a few reasons for disliking the term: it’s imprecise, it’s misleading, and it is unintelligible to the majority of literate adults. And yet I’m torn, because I also think that it captures a very real tendency. I worry that overusing shaggy theoretical terminology can both alienate readers and result in vague or meaningless writing. But the underlying phenomenon that “neoliberalism” describes has occurred, and I agree with the perspective laid out by Mike Konzcal, who says:
I find that the term neoliberalism generally confuses more than it enlightens. I prefer when people just refer directly to what they are criticizing, be it the expansion of the marketplace into our everyday lives or the Democrats’ turn away from the New Deal. … [Yet] there’s a good reason the term has become popular.
Let me explain why I think “neoliberalism” is an important term, albeit one that should rarely be used by magazine writers who would like people to actually read their articles. It captures the tendency of people who are nominally “on the left” to make arguments based on conservative premises. For example: Republicans argue that their tax cut will increase GDP, reduce the deficit, and reduce taxes for the middle class. Democrats reply that the tax cut will not increase GDP, will not reduce the deficit, and will not reduce the middle-class’s tax burden. Both parties are arguing around a shared premise: the goal is to cut taxes for the middle class, reduce the deficit, and grow GDP. But traditional liberalism, before the “neo” variety emerged, would have made its case on the basis of some quite different premises. Instead of arguing that Democrats are actually the party that will reduce the middle class’ taxes, it would make the case that taxes are important, because it’s only through taxes that we can improve schools, infrastructure, healthcare, and poverty relief. Instead of participating in the race to cut taxes and the deficit, Old Liberalism is based on a set of moral ideas about what we owe to one another.
Now, one reason I dislike the “neoliberalism” framework is that I’m not sure how much this nostalgic conception of the Great Liberalism Of Times Past should be romanticized. But it’s obvious that there’s a great deal of difference between New Deal/Great Society rhetoric and “Actually We’re The Real Job Creators/Tax-Cutters/GDP Growers.” And it’s also true that over the last decades, certain pro-market ideological premises have wormed their way into the mind of ordinary liberals to the point that debates occur within a very narrow economic framework.
Let me give you a very clear example. Libertarian economist Bryan Caplan has a new book out called The Case Against Education. It argues that the public school system is a waste of time and money and should be destroyed. Caplan says that students are right to wonder “when they will ever use” the things they are being taught. They won’t, he says, because they’re not being taught any skills they will actually need in the job market. Instead, education functions mostly as “signaling”: a degree shows an employer that you are the type of person who works hard and is responsible, not that you have actually learned particular things that you need. Credentials, Caplan says, are mostly meaningless. He argues that we should drastically cut public school funding, make education more like job training, get rid of history, music, and the arts, and “deregulate and destigmatize child labor.” Essentially, Caplan believes that education should be little more than skills training for jobs, and it’s failing at that.
Now here’s where “neoliberalism” comes in. Caplan’s argument is obviously based on right-wing economic premises: markets should sort everything out, the highest good is to create value for your employers, etc. But let’s look at a “liberal” response. In The Washington Monthly, Kevin Carey has a biting critique of Caplan’s book, which he says is based on a “childish” philosophy. Carey says that education is, in fact useful for more than signaling:
Caplan is not wrong about the existence of signaling and its kissing cousin, credentialism, which describes the tendency of job categories to accrue more degree requirements, sometimes unnecessarily, over time. But these are banal and unchallenged ideas in the economics profession. … In his 2001 Nobel lecture, [Michael] Spence warned that people who use job markets to illustrate signaling run the risk of concluding, wrongly, that education doesn’t contribute to productivity. This wrongheaded argument is the essence of The Case Against Education… Eric Hanushek, a conservative economist and well-known skeptic of public school funding, has documented a strong relationship between average scores on international tests and the growth rates of national economies. Put simply, well-educated nations become prosperous nations, and no country has become well educated without large, sustained investments in public education.
Carey mounts a strong defense of public education against Caplan’s attack. But look at how he does it. Caplan has argued that education doesn’t actually make students more productive or give them skills useful for thriving in the economy. Carey replies that while this is partly true, education does actually increase productivity, as we can see when we look across nations. Everyone in the discussion, however, is operating on the implicit premise that the measure of whether education is successful is “productivity.” And because of that, no matter how strong the liberal argument is, no matter how stingingly critical it may be of libertarianism or privatization, it has already ceded the main point. We all agree that education is about maximizing students’ value to the economy, we just disagree about the degree to which public education successfully does that, and whether the solution is to fix the system or get rid of it. The debate becomes one of empirics rather than values.
Carey doesn’t make a case for an alternative “liberal” notion of education,  and doesn’t question the values underlying the “banal and unchallenged ideas in the economics profession.” But unless liberalism is to be something more than “a difference of opinion over the correct way to maximize productivity,” it’s important to defend a wholly different set of principles. Otherwise, what if it turns out that providing art and music classes is a drag on productivity? What if teaching students history turns out to make them worse workers, because they begin to see a resemblance between their bosses and the robber barons? What if the study of philosophy makes laborers less compliant and docile? If we argue that music is actually economically useful, then we’ll have no defense of music if it turns out not to be useful. Instead, we need to argue that whether music is economically useful has nothing to do with whether students deserve to be exposed to it.
(Continue Reading)
87 notes · View notes
wil917-blog · 7 years
Text
The Liberal Perspective
The way I see it, one of the main differences between liberals and conservatives is the idea of personal responsibility. A conservative believes that individual hard work and dedication are the main ingredients necessary to achieve success in life, and that money and material comforts are personally earned rather than freely handed out. Wealth is therefore a measure of talent, willingness to take risks, perseverance in attaining goals, and most importantly, good old sweat and hard work. 
Simply put, conservatives believe that they are personally responsible for their successes and failures in life.
From the liberal perspective, these ideas certainly have merit and we agree with overall idea, which is that hard work should be rewarded, and that the harder you work, the more you should earn. Of course someone who works hard should be rewarded with a good job and a high standard of living, while someone who spends all day lazing around ignoring their studies should not live in a mansion and drive a Rolls-Royce.
But liberals see an additional layer of nuance that is not usually part of the conservative point of view. Liberals put individual successes and failures into the larger social context. From the liberal perspective, no one earns 100% of what they have. There are many reasons for this (which I will describe in more detail below) but one is simply that people’s successes build upon the achievements of millions of other people, upon the accumulated wealth of an advanced civilization which developed for thousands of years before they were born, and therefore cannot be claimed as solely the product of their own efforts.
Conservatives believe that nothing is handed out for free, but in fact, each of us, at the moment we are born, becomes a part of some existing socioeconomic environment, and is handed the collective wisdom and achievements of billions of people who have lived, worked, and died before us. 
With this idea, I am just trying to introduce the concept that no one can say that they personally earned everything they have in life, because we all rely on the collective achievements of everyone alive today and everyone who has come before us. We live in an advanced civilization that is several thousand years old, a civilization that has discovered how to release the energy of individual atoms, send rockets beyond the edge of the solar system, and edit our own DNA. We should, at least on some level, acknowledge this free gift we were handed. I’m not saying we need to thank Newton and Einstein each time we use the GPS to find a new restaurant, but to at least have an appreciation for the fact that all of our personal comforts come from the labor and talent of millions of other people.
The points I made above are a bit “out there” and probably more profound than what an everyday liberal would usually be thinking about. At a more concrete level, though, the basic idea is the same. We rely on the frameworks and structures of civilization in order to achieve success in life. An important category of products and services we rely on are those funded by the government through taxation. These include roads, bridges, ports, dams, electrical grids, the patent office and copyright protection laws, police departments, fire departments, the military, the EPA, the USDA, the FDA, the consumer financial protection bureau, financial regulations, PELL grants, laws enforcing business contracts, bankruptcy laws, traffic regulations, the court system, FEMA and other disaster management and aid programs, the CSB which investigates industrial hazardous chemical emergencies, and on and on. Many conservatives complain of big government, but these services are here to create an environment where individual people can build a successful life, and should be thought of as programs paid for by everyone, for everyone. They provide a supporting structure which we all rely on, whether we realize it or not, to build our wealth and happiness.
The majority of liberals, including myself, favor a capitalist economy, so I will not spend any time arguing for other economic systems. Therefore, we generally agree that the mixed economy that we have now (a free market with some government intervention) works well, and that this is a good model for setting prices and exchanging goods and services.
To a liberal, though, there are very important limitations that must be placed upon our capitalist system in order to make the society that it produces “fair.” Chief among these is the problem of wealth accumulation. This is a serious point of disagreement between liberals and conservatives, so I will look into the issue closely.
I have made two major points so far: (1) capitalism is, in general, a good system for society to be organized around, and (2) no one fully earns 100% of what they have, because they relied upon (a) the previous generations of people who built up society to what it is today, and (b) the frameworks and structures of that society, including the services of government collectively paid for by everyone. The result is that we are all very tiny elements in a vast, interconnected, interwoven society of hundreds of millions of people, with any one person in this system very much relying on everyone else to achieve a comfortable life. This collective effort is central and essential. We are a social species, after all. 
Because of the inter-reliance and cooperation built into this system, a liberal would see it as unfair if any one person pulls too far ahead of the pack in terms of the wealth they have obtained in life. The vast majority of Americans, for example, make less than $250k per year. Although this is definitely a large number, let’s call an annual income of less than $250k “normal,” and let’s assume that these incomes are proportional to effort. By “proportional to effort” I simply mean that someone who works twice as hard makes roughly twice as much money, someone who works three times as hard makes three times as much money, and so on. 
This is of course hard to measure and very subjective, but I think that many people (including both liberals and conservatives) would accept the premise that people who earn $250k are more talented and have worked harder, and therefore have earned and “deserve” that higher income, and that a person who earns $40k is still making enough to make ends meet, but may lack similar work ethic, talent, and skills. Additionally, this difference in incomes is an important motivating force in the capitalist system, compelling people to work harder (and therefore make more contributions to society as a whole) in order to make that higher income.
The problem comes when individuals start accumulating wealth that far exceeds their efforts compared to everyone else. Simply put, is a man earning $50 million per year really working 1,000 times harder than someone earning $50k per year? Even if conservatives have other reasons for supporting the ability of people to make such large incomes, I think that, if pressed, they would agree that, no, he is not really working 1,000 times harder than the average Joe.
Does he deserve to have a large income? Definitely. He is making very important contributions to society, whether by managing a company that sells life-saving pharmaceuticals or one that manufactures essential agricultural equipment. Whatever it is, he is providing some socially-useful product or service which people are paying for, and the capitalist economy is rewarding him for his work.
But there is no reason to assert that he should individually keep such a large fraction of the profit of the company he manages, nor is it objectively true that he “earned” or “deserves” it. You see, the capitalist system we have chosen is entirely a product of the imaginations of human beings, and everything about it sprouted from the minds of ordinary men and women. The capitalist system is not a “law of nature” or some profound “universal truth.” It is a man-made entity, and all parts of it are arbitrary. Yes, it is a very good system as we have devised it, but no, just because a CEO makes $50 million in the capitalist system does not mean that most people would agree it is fair for him to keep that amount. 
Liberals see it as an unfair accumulation of wealth, simply because we think that it is not possible for any person to truly earn $25,000 per hour in a country where poverty, homelessness, lack of access to basic health care, and other societal problems still exist. In our view, he is not working 1,000 times harder than the average person, and we do not believe it is justified that he should rise so significantly above the rest of the society which supported him in the first place.
Moreover, to even be in the position of earning that amount means that this CEO is relying more heavily on the institutions of government and society than the rest of us, whether through the patent and copyright office which is protecting his intellectual property with taxpayer dollars, to the highway system which distributes his goods to all corners of the country, to the FDA which makes sure that his products are safe so that consumers have the confidence to buy them. Somehow, his ability to accumulate wealth has become decoupled from the notion that working harder leads to a proportional increase in success. Liberals believe that this should be rectified.
And so we come to the idea of taxation. Everyone is taxed to pay for government services, as we know. The general view is that, on average, we should raise about 20% of the GDP in taxes to pay for all of the services necessary to generate that GDP. Liberal policies often lead to higher taxation (which I will explain more below), so let’s say that amount is 25% for a liberal government. 
We then simply assert that the tax system should be devised in such a way that taxes are paid on the basis of one’s ability to pay. The less one makes, the less one is benefiting from the services of government, and therefore the less one pays in taxes, and vice versa. This distribution of taxes naturally pushes the tax burden on higher income brackets, with the wealthiest people paying the highest marginal tax rates. This is not a punishment to wealthy people, it is an inevitable and necessary outcome of a system in which taxes are paid on an “as-able” basis. Poor people do not become rich off this system, and rich people remain rich after their taxes are taken. There are no massive redistributions of wealth in this setup, and everyone’s after-tax income remains proportional to their effort and level of hard work. 
And for the very wealthy, like the CEO making $50 million, his after-tax income may fall to $20 million. A $30 million drop!? Well, yes. He had more of an ability to pay, and so he has been taxed more. And, very very importantly, this has (from the liberal perspective) improved the proportionality between his effort and his income. It is at least more reasonable to assume that he deserves closer to $10,000 per hour for his effort, rather than $250,000, and that he works closer to 400 times harder than the average Joe, rather than 1,000 times harder. Of course, it is still hard to imagine he is working that much harder, but we are not trying to completely re-write the rules of capitalism. 
We are content with this modification allowing for more reasonable incomes among the very wealthy, and a better proportionality between their incomes and the level of effort with which they work compared to average workers.
That’s it. That’s the core of the liberal perspective concerning wealth accumulating and taxation. It is about acknowledging that capitalism works well, but in the realm of very high incomes it becomes necessary to make modifications, through tax policy, to achieve a fairer economic outcome that helps to ensure that the income vs. effort proportionality does not diverge so significantly from the rest of the workforce. 
This has the added benefit of allowing this additional tax revenue to go toward other social programs, the most important of which is universal health care. The liberal view of healthcare is very consistent with the philosophy outlined above about fair outcomes for everyone. Unexpected disasters happen in life, and the premise of universal healthcare is to give everyone the peace of mind that if they are the unlucky victims of such events, they will never have to worry about going bankrupt or selling their homes in order to pay their medical bills. 
3 notes · View notes
the-utmost-bound · 7 years
Text
The Happiness Hypothesis: Chapter 4, “The Faults of Others”
[NOTE: I am just outlining this book for my own edification; I don’t expect anyone else to read this post.]
This was the second chapter on how humans related to each other.  In the previous chapter, Haidt explained how fairness and cooperation are able to hold society together.  In this chapter, Haidt explains how hypocrisy threatens cooperation.
In particular, we are able to notice when other people are acting unfairly, but we don’t notice when we ourselves do it.
Relevant quotes from ancient literature:
Matthew 7:3-5: Why do you see the speck in your neighbor’s eye, but do not notice the log in your own eye? ... You hypocrite, first take the log out of your own eye, and then you will see clearly to take the speck out of your neighbor’s eye.
Buddha: It is easy to see the faults of others, but difficult to see one’s own faults.  One shows the faults of others like chaff winnowed in the wind, but one conceals one’s own faults as a cunning gambler conceals his dice.
Haidt opens the chapter by saying:
One of the most universal pieces of advice from across cultures and eras is that we are all hypocrites, and in our condemnation of others’ hypocrisy we only compound our own.  Social psychologists have recently isolated the mechanisms that make us blind to the logs in our own eyes.  The moral implications of these findings are disturbing; indeed, they challenge our greatest moral certainties.  But the implications can be liberating, too, freeing you from destructive moralism and divisive self-righteousness.
The first part of the chapter talks about why we’re hypocrites, and describes the psychological research on hypocrisy.
The second part of the chapter explains how these mechanisms lead to polarization and conflict in society.
Keeping Up Appearances
Tit-for-tat is the optimal strategy when you can fully observe the other player’s actions.
“In real life, however, you don’t react to what someone did; you react only to what you think she did, and the gap between action and perception is bridged by the art of impression management.”
So a better strategy might be to defect but convince the other person that you’ve cooperated.  Haidt calls this “Macchiavellian tit-for-tat”.
The best way to convince others that you’ve cooperated is to convince yourself.  Hypocrisy works best when you believe your own lies.
Haidt says:
We are well-armed for battle in a Machiavellian world of reputation manipulation, and one of our most important weapons is the delusion that we are non-combatants.
Find Your Inner Lawyer
So how does hypocrisy work?  How do we manage to convince ourselves that we’re not at fault?
Recall from Chapter 1 that the rider often acts like a lawyer, arguing on behalf of the elephant’s beliefs.
When given some question (e.g. “should we increase minimum wage?”) the elephant immediately comes up with some intuition (yes or no) and then the rider reaches for some “pseudoevidence” to support it (e.g. an anecdote about someone who is living on minimum wage and can’t support a family).
Once people have this piece of anecdata, they’re done; they don’t look any further for more evidence, and they certainly don’t try to find evidence that argues against their position.  Haidt calls this “a one-sided search for supporting evidence only”.
In low-stakes situations, if someone else gives you an argument against your position, you might end up changing your mind; you just won’t reach for those counterarguments yourself.
In high-stakes situations, people are even more determined to find supporting evidence, and are less open to arguments against it.
“Over and over again, studies show that people set out on a cognitive mission to bring back reasons to support their preferred belief or action.  And because we are usually successful in this mission, we end up with the illusion of objectivity.  We really believe that our position is rationally and objectively justified.”
The Rose-Colored Mirror
When playing Machiavellian tit-for-tat, you need to carefully craft your self-presentation to appear virtuous.
But since everyone else is playing Machiavellian tit-for-tat too, you need to be wary of their claims to virtue.
It turns out that we have a realistic estimate of other people’s virtue, but an overly rosy picture of our own.
A majority of Americans and Europeans rate themselves as above average on skills and virtues.
When asked to predict how much they’ll donate in a charitable event, people predict other people’s donations accurately but wildly overestimate their own.
People believe they do a larger percentage of teamwork or chores than they actually do.
These self-serving biases “can make people feel that they deserve more than they do, thereby setting the stage for endless disputes with other people who feel equally over-entitled.”
I’m Right; You’re Biased
Across many studies, even when people are told about self-serving biases, they still fail to correct for them.
Why are people so blind to their own biases?
Some of this can be explained by “naive realism”, the belief that we see things as they really are.
Since we have access to objective truth, if someone else disagrees, it must be because they are blinded by religion or ideology.
We perceive others as biased, but ourselves as just seeing things the way they really are.
At the end of that section, Haidt starts talking about how our hypocrisy and biases lead to polarization in society.
Naive realism exists at the group level as well as the individual: “My group is right because we see things as they are.  Those who disagree are obviously biased by their religion, their ideology, or their self-interest.”
This makes it easy to see the world in terms of good vs. evil, where your group is good and the other group is evil.
Satan Satisfies
Crime and danger are decreasing, but people are always looking for some evil enemy to fight against.
It used to be communism, or Satan himself.  These days it’s homosexuals (if you’re conservative) or racists/homophones (if you’re liberal).
All of these villains share three characteristics: “They are invisible (you can’t identify the evil one from appearance alone); their evil spreads by contagion, making it vital to protect impressionable young people (for example from communist ideas, homosexual teachers, or stereotypes on television); and the villains can be defeated only if we all pull together as a team.”
People need an enemy in order to justify banding together as a group.  And being on a holy mission gives people a sense of purpose.
“We are thus convinced of our own virtue, but quick to see bias, greed, and duplicity in others.  We are often corrected about others’ motives, but as any conflict escalates we begin to exaggerate grossly, to weave a story in which pure virtue (our side) is in a battle with pure vice (theirs).”
The Myth of Pure Evil
A psychologist named Baumeister studied people’s perception of evil.
He looked at evil from both the perspective of the perpetrator and the victim; we tend to think the victim was blameless and the perpetrator was evil, but there’s usually more to the story than that.  Usually the victim did something to incite the perpetrator.  “Most murders result from an escalating cycle of provocation and retaliation[.]”
That’s not to say that both parties are equally to blame; the perpetrator might be completely overreacting (based on the same self-serving biases Haidt has been talking about in the whole chapter).
But in general, one side is not purely evil and the other purely good.
Yet we seem to have a psychological need to see things in those terms.
He calls this “the myth of pure evil”.  This includes ideas like “the evildoers are pure in their evil motives (they have no motives for their actions beyond sadism and greed); victims are pure in their victimhood (they did nothing to bring about their victimization); and evil comes from outside and is associated with a group or force that attacks our group.  Furthermore, anyone who questions the application of the myth, who dares muddy the waters of moral certainty, is in league with evil.”
This causes a polarization between groups that can lead to violence and war.
In reality, evil has four main causes: greed/ambition, pure sadism, high self-esteem, and moral idealism.  We think of the first two as causing most evil, but actually they don’t.  High self-esteem causes evil when people lash out violently to defend against threats to their ego.  Moral idealism causes evil when people think that the ends justify the means.  “The major atrocities of the 20th century were carried out largely either by men who thought they were creating a utopia or else by men who believed they were defending their homeland or tribe from attack.”
Finding the Great Way
We live in a world that our minds infuse with significance.  “That is, the world we live in is not really one made of rocks, trees, and physical objects; it is a world of insults, opportunities, status symbols, betrayals, saints, and sinners.”
Our minds weave us this world of significance, out of our self-serving biases and hypocrisy.  When you look at it from the outside, all these conflicts seem pointless and silly.  So what do you do about it?
The first step is to view it as a game, in which each person plays out his part.  This is what’s taught in the Bhagavad Gita.  Hinduism tells you to keep playing the game, but with a sense of irony and self-awareness.  Buddhism tells you to quit the game entirely.
Meditation and cognitive therapy can also help us with self-awareness of our own hypocrisy.
In order to get out of this trap it’s good to start looking for the log in your own eye.  When you can see your own contribution to conflicts, it makes it harder to be angry and to perpetuate the disagreements.
It’s hard to see the log in our own eye, because we’re programmed by evolution to be moralistic hypocrites.  But if we can do it, then it can help decrease conflict and lead to happiness.
Haidt doesn’t give a conclusion about whether he agrees with the ancient sayings, but it’s pretty clear that he thinks they are right about our hypocrisy.
1 note · View note
bluewatsons · 4 years
Text
Dayna Bowen Matthew, Justice and the Struggle for the Soul of Medicaid, Virginia Public Law and Legal Theory Research Paper No. 2020-31
Abstract
The soul of Medicaid is and always has been to achieve justice in health care. Medicaid at its inception was designed to ensure that the most vulnerable members of society are not excluded from access to good health that all others enjoy. Yet, as the title of this symposium aptly reflects, “The Struggle for the Soul of Medicaid” remains vulnerable to repeated and relentless political attacks. Why is this so, given that program finances care for nearly 64 million Americans in all 51 states?
This article posits that Medicaid is vulnerable because our nation’s commitment to justice in health care remains uncertain. Historically, our commitment to justice in America has been limited by our willingness to bear the cost required to achieve justice. Moreover, our commitment has often been further limited by our inability to empathize with people who need Medicaid assistance in order to gain access to health care. We have limited the program to the “categorically” needy. Those who “deserve” help gaining access to health care. And more recently, some have used work requirements to ensure that Medicaid health benefits are meted out only to those worthy of receiving them. In contrast, the legislative purpose of the Act was so clear to its proponents, and so aligned with their shared foundational values as well as the values upon which our democracy rests, that in 1965, little more needed to be said in defense of Medicaid. That it provided a nationwide safety net for the many of society’s poor and destitute to receive health care, regardless of their ability to pay, may have been justification enough for the program
However simply identifying justice as the ethical value that lies at the soul of the Medicaid program cannot save the program. Justice takes many forms, and its many expressions can serve to justify competing and even mutually exclusive ends where Medicaid is concerned. Egalitarian conceptualizations inspire Medicaid’s communitarian commitment to provide access to health care to for society’s neediest equalize the opportunity to participate in society. Utilitarian justice may aim to maximize societal health but not might accomplish these ends by identifying some poor or needy members of society as more deserving than others. And libertarian justice ideals counsel minimizing the cost burden that Medicaid places on non- beneficiaries. Notwithstanding the epistemological struggle, the Medicaid program remains quite popular with Americans, regardless of party affiliation. Republicans learned this during their failed multiple efforts to repeal-and-replace the Affordable Care Act.
This article argues that the justice that originally motivated the Medicaid mission has survived as the program’s chief animating principle. That egalitarian vision of justice compels policy-makers to stretch Medicaid’s already scarce and over-burdened resources far beyond the clinical setting to rectify inequitable distribution of the social and environmental risk factors that disproportionately threaten the health of Medicaid-eligible populations. The unfairness of this additional burden on the program is not trivial. We already ask far too much of the program. Yet, the point of this article is to clarify why and how Medicaid can do even more than it does today to fulfill the mandates of justice, and thereby contribute substantially to nation-wide health equity.
Of all the forms of inequality, injustice in healthcare is the most shocking and inhuman.1 --Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr.
Speak up for those who cannot speak for themselves; ensure justice for those being crushed. Yes, speak up for the poor and helpless, and see that they get justice. --Proverbs 31:8-9 (NLT)
Chief among the structural forces creating unjust access to health-promoting opportunities and resources is subordination based on markers of perceived difference, such as race, gender, sexuality, and class. . . . From this perspective, the problem of health disparities is ultimately a problem of justice.2 -- Angela P. Harris and Aysha Pamukcu
I. Introduction
This article posits that the soul of Medicaid is and always has been to achieve justice in health care. Yet, as the title of this symposium aptly reflects, “The Struggle for the Soul of Medicaid” continues because our nation’s commitment to justice in health care remains open to question. Historically, our commitment to justice in America has always been limited by our willingness to bear the cost required to achieve justice. Moreover, our commitment has often been further limited by our inability to empathize with people who need Medicaid assistance in order to gain access to health care. We have limited the program to the “categorically” needy. Those who “deserve” help gaining access to health care. And more recently, some have used work requirements to ensure that Medicaid health benefits are meted out only to those worthy of receiving them. In contrast, Medicaid at its inception was designed to ensure that the most vulnerable members of society are not excluded from access to good health that all others enjoy. The program was premised on the fairness of affording everyone an equal opportunity to be healthy. Thus, justice is the “soul” of the Medicaid program. Put another way, justice – in the Rawlsian sense – is a core principle and essential reason for the Medicaid program’s existence. Justice, in a spiritual sense, is the purpose that transcends the Medicaid program’s physical existence. However, to many, justice is strained by Medicaid’s spiraling costs, which, driven by the increasing underlying cost of health care, have dramatically increased the shared burden of paying for the access to health care that Medicaid affords. Against the reality of scarce rather than unlimited resources available for health care, the true struggle for the soul of Medicaid lies in the unresolved debate about justice itself. The complex struggle for the soul of Medicaid explored in this article examines conflicting views of justice and their implications for the direction and purpose of the Medicaid program. These views are in tension with the cost that achieving or failing to achieve health justice imposes on us all. Put simply, the thesis of this article is that we must add to Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr.’s exhortation—that of all forms of inequality, injustice in health care is not only the most shocking and inhuman, but it is also the costliest.
Because Medicaid was passed without significant legislative debate, leading scholars have suggested the program was merely an “afterthought” to the more politically popular Medicare program.3 This may be true. However, I suggest another view of the paucity of Medicaid’s legislative record. Rather than the conclusion that the program “involved significantly less philosophical or political thought” than its public health insurance counterpart, it may have been that the legislative purpose of the Act was so clear to its proponents, and so aligned with their shared foundational values as well as the values upon which our democracy rests, that in 1965, little more needed to be said in defense of Medicaid. That it provided a nationwide safety net for the many of society’s poor and destitute to receive health care, regardless of their ability to pay, may have been justification enough for the program.4 By this reckoning, the Medicaid proposal satisfied those seeking to incrementally inch ever closer toward their ultimate goal of ensuring universal access to health care, by ensuring access to health insurance for all.5 Plausibly, this is the reason Medicaid overcame the objections of those vehemently opposed to “socialized medicine,” and wary of the federal government’s interference in local affairs, may have nonetheless seen the need for providing at least temporary aid and assistance to those who are destitute.6 Today, the struggle for the soul of Medicaid is ongoing not merely because our nation has wandered woefully far away from its fundamental goal of ensuring access to basic medical services for all, but also because the cost of the program has grown exponentially. According to historians Rosemary and Robert Stevens, Medicaid was enacted “amid great hope on the part of the liberals as the so-called ‘sleeper’ of the Social Security Act of 1965.”7 Yet, soon after it passed, commentators were hailing the program a failure because it was so expensive.8 In its first five years, Medicaid exceeded projections by $5.5 billion per year while it was originally projected to cost less than $1 billion per year.9 The program continues to be expensive. In Fiscal Year 2017, total federal and state Medicaid spending was $577 billion. It is the third largest program in the domestic federal budget, equaling 9.5% of all federal spending. Critics of the program have sought to contain its costs, most commonly by converting funding sources to block grants.10 Some go so far as to disparage its participants, most infamously by labeling them “welfare queens.”11 In both instances, the cost containment efforts are focused on patients—the recipients of the Medicaid dollar—as though they represent the primary solution for containing Medicaid costs. I argue here that they do not. Block grants may contain the share of costs borne by state governments, but block grants do “nothing to reduce the cost of care” delivery.12 Thus, as health care costs rise, Medicaid beneficiaries in block grant states will either receive less care, or find they are no longer eligible for care.13
Notwithstanding the epistemological struggle, the Medicaid program remains quite popular with Americans, regardless of party affiliation. Republicans learned this during their failed multiple efforts to repeal-and-replace the Affordable Care Act.14 The majority of Democrats (eighty-four percent), Independents (seventy-six percent), and Republicans (sixty-one percent) hold a favorable view of Medicaid.15 According to a Kaiser Family Foundation poll conducted in 2017, most think Medicaid works well for low-income people and few Americans want a decrease in federal spending on Medicaid. When asked to think about the country’s health priorities in the federal budget, few (twelve percent) say they want to see the President and Congress decrease spending on Medicaid, while four in ten say they want increased spending.16 About half (forty-seven percent) say they want the President and Congress to keep Medicaid spending about the same. Moreover, the public generally opposes Medicaid block grants, but does favor allowing states to have more flexibility to determine which groups of people and what services are covered under the program.17 The reason for this general support, I suggest, is that the majority of Americans share the core fairness principles that animate Medicaid as a way to give all people access to health care. In short, they see the program as a way for the country to “do justice.”18
This article argues that the struggle for the soul of Medicaid is driven by competing views of justice. Using broad strokes, I suggest that the three major perspectives on justice have all influenced formation and reform efforts that shape the Medicaid program. Medicaid has overcome objections and survived efforts to eliminate it altogether because the program, in some form, continues to serve utilitarian, egalitarian, and libertarian views of justice. While I do not take a deep dive here into the theoretical or philosophical scholarship, I do in the end conclude that a Rawlsian approach to the problem of health inequity counsels that despite its flaws, Medicaid is the appropriate program and most hopeful public policy vehicle through which to offer fair equality of opportunity for healthy lives to low-wealth communities in this country.
This article argues that the justice motivation at the core of the Medicaid mission compels policy-makers to stretch its already scarce and over-burdened resources far beyond the clinical setting to rectify inequitable distribution of the social and environmental risk factors that disproportionately threaten the health of Medicaid-eligible populations. The unfairness of this additional burden on the program is not trivial. Medicaid is a program that currently reimburses physician providers eighty-eight cents on the dollar and yet, together with the Children’s Health Insurance Program (CHIP), covers over seventy-four million enrollees, more than any other single health insurance program in the nation. We already ask far too much of the program. Yet, the point of this article is to clarify why this is so, and to argue that Medicaid can do even more to fulfill its stated and intended goals.
To justify my claim, I will appeal to the heart and soul of what Medicaid is intended to do. I hope to demonstrate that the foundational objectives of the program remain ones to which the majority of Americans are committed. Similarly, those who are critics or opponents of Medicaid remain similarly aligned with those who, at its inception, misunderstood or misrepresented its purpose. Clarity on its purpose might dispel some myths that stand in the way of the program reaching its full potential and could rekindle courageous support for the program’s commitment to reimburse for care that is “medically necessary.” The article proceeds in three parts. First, I will use evidence of the debate that surrounded Medicaid’s enactment to demonstrate its distributive roots. I conclude that, at its inception, Medicaid was designed to serve egalitarian justice. Second, I will suggest that the reform efforts that appear most threatening to the Medicaid program may best be understood as efforts to serve justice from utilitarian and libertarian perspectives. Yet, I suggest, the reason for the program’s enduring popularity lies in the fact that more Rawlsian—that is, equitable—conceptualizations of Medicaid continue to capture the public imagination and are, in fact, most consistent with the program’s initial purpose. Therefore, in Part V of the article, I propose fully embrace the relationship between Medicaid and the social justice model articulated by Madison Powers and Ruth Faden in 2006. I apply this model to argue for using Medicaid as a way to finance equal access to the social determinants of health beyond health care in order to meaningfully contribute to health equity in low wealth communities nation-wide. This, I argue, is what justice demands of Medicaid, and of our nation.
II. Egalitarian Justice in Medicaid: Health Care for the Needy
Judith Moore and David Smith have explained clearly that the Medicaid program has “strong roots” in the “public welfare system.”19 The medical payments offered under Medicaid and its predecessor programs have always been linked to the recipients’ confirmed status as “needy.”20 At first, mere poverty was sufficient to qualify one for Medicaid eligibility. In 1950, the first Federal public assistance for medical payments provided matching funds to health care vendors (i.e., providers), but only for people who were receiving cash welfare payments.21 Later, in 1960, when the Kerr-Mills legislation, Medicaid’s immediate predecessor, authorized Medical Assistance to the Aged, that program’s eligible recipients were identified as the indigent elderly—not just the elderly. The replacement program was conceived of as a way to improve on the Kerr-Mills program which had become an embarrassment because it fell far short of meeting the basic medical needs of the elderly. However, poverty was required to justify eligibility even for the elderly.22
Like its predecessor, the Kerr-Mills program, Medicaid was designed by its proponents to ensure that low-income people received at least basic medical care. Health care, it was thought, should not be denied to anyone simply because they could not pay. This notion of medical egalitarianism did not seek to make everyone equal recipients of the same health care or beneficiaries of the same health outcomes. Instead, Medicaid began as traditional health insurance for poor people who feel into identified categories of need.23 At its inception, it was an add-on to cash welfare benefit, covering very low income single parents and their children, the aged, blind, and disabled.24 The point was to distribute medical care to those who could not afford to pay for it themselves, but nevertheless were entitled to receive care on the basis of their incapacity. Thus, the program was driven by the communitarian principle of shared responsibility for the neediest among us. As Medicaid’s eligibility expanded steadily beyond its initial base, covering additional populations such as children with two parents and pregnant women, its egalitarian motivations were tested. Lawmakers sought to define eligibility criteria that seemed fair. Analyst Alan Weil explains Medicaid’s egalitarian function this way:
If money is at the heart of debates over Medicaid, the millions of indigent people whose varied and complex medical needs are met by the program are its soul. The amount of human suffering the program alleviates is immense. In the absence of a comprehensive health care system that meets the acute and chronic care needs of the nation, Medicaid perfectly fits the metaphor of the “safety net.”25
Arguably, a conceptual misunderstanding of the nature of poverty was one of the reasons the “safety net” metaphor has frayed. At the beginning of the program, policy-makers constructed a program that was designed to help people on a temporary basis; it was thought that the Medicaid safety-net could provide quick fix to poverty and return families to live unsupported in the general economy. Instead, the program’s costs continued to climb as it became clear that needs of covered individuals persisted as long as the complex structures that reinforce poverty such as mis-education, under-employment, and inadequate housing, persisted.26 Therefore, the Medicaid dollar became a less effective remedy for needy populations, and thus became subject to selectively allocating benefits among competing, needy populations. Policymakers faced the perplexing conundrum of determining who was deserving of Medicaid eligibility and who was not.27 The debate also shifted to identifying what services should be covered and which should not. Initially, Medicaid was a program to provide just one item in the safety net: medical care. It provided medical care to poor families with children, to the elderly, and to the disabled.28 Congress tied Medicaid eligibility to receipt of cash assistance under welfare (Aid to Families with Dependent Children [AFDC]) or Supplemental Security Income (SSI) for the elderly and disabled (noncash recipients).29 Over time, poverty alone became a less satisfactory criterion for Medicaid eligibility as policy-makers recognized that poverty alone did not define neediness. Funds shifted away from covering only the poor, to also covering the chronically ill and elderly. During this shift, Medicaid eligibility expanded to cover selected non-poor members of society, but the program covered this expansion by excluding some low-income recipients who were neither ill nor elderly.30 In other words, Medicaid contained costs by covering only the very poor, but not those whose poverty did not place them at the very lowest economic strata. By 1985, the program reimbursed medical care for only forty percent of those below the federal poverty level, revealing that the philanthropically motivated soul of Medicaid had grown less compelled to address health needs due to mere poverty, than health needs due to frailty.31
The soul of Medicaid has also been challenged by federalism concerns. Stakeholders committed to minimizing the federal government’s intrusion into health policy, while protecting states’ control over their health care systems, have been outspoken opponents of the Medicaid program from the beginning. These opponents included the majority of physicians, hospitals, and health care providers.32 The American Medical Association (AMA) wrote the following about the earliest, most limited versions of Medicaid proposed in 1956:
The American Medical Association is vigorously and firmly opposed to this step. First, we see no need for the establishment of medical care as a fifth and separate category of Federal aid in public assistance programs. Pooling arrangements now available to the States under the existing program can accomplish more flexibly and less dangerously all the new proposals seek.33
The AMA, by this argument seemed to assert that the soul of Medicaid was to serve patient safety and perhaps state and local government autonomy. However, closer examination of the examples the AMA summoned in support of its federalism position quickly reveal that the providers’ concerns went far beyond patient needs or states rights. At bottom, it appears from their rhetoric, that the AMA’s expressed concerns were driven first by the conviction that the soul of Medicaid was subordinate to the professional (and financial) interests of health care providers.
[S]uch a new program would burden the community with regulations and restrictions inconsistent with local problems, local laws, or local customs. As an example, amendments to the aid-to-blind program under the Social Security Act have granted to optometrists since 1952 the privilege of diagnosing pathological conditions of the eye. This privilege, until 1952, had been uniformly denied to them by state licensure laws.34
Where providers were concerned, it seems the Medicaid program was beholden to protect the privilege of some health professionals as against others. Moreover, these providers appeared not only to object vigorously to the federal intrusion upon their profession, but also espoused a particular view of the proper extent and duration of neediness. Before its enactment, the AMA declared itself vigorously opposed to the proposed changes in the medical care provisions of the public assistance sections of the Social Security Act. We are opposed to those changes because they are needless, wasteful, dangerous, and contrary to the established policy of gradual Federal withdrawal from local public assistance programs.35
Finally, the AMA’s opposition made clear that in its view, the soul of Medicaid must be protected from a creeping philosophy of universal insurance. Many saw this as an idea born of socialist ideology, and contrary to the interests of the medical industrial complex and American values:36
[W]e cannot escape the conclusion that injection of medical care as a separately matched category of expenditure under public assistance is only a forerunner to the injection of medical care as a categorical benefit under old age and survivors insurance. You are aware of the overwhelming rejection by both the American people and the medical profession of this philosophy. As physicians, we must continue to oppose programs which, in the guise of improving medical care, will lead to the destruction of the system which has produced the best medical care ever enjoyed by any people.37
At the outset, the ideals Medicaid’s proponents sought to serve—to equally distribute access to health care to both wealthy and low-wealth individuals—conflicted with its opponents’ goals of professional autonomy, federalism, and the propriety of offering long-term assistance to non-disabled, needy adults. As a result, the egalitarian goals of the Medicaid program have been tested and limited by the effort to identify just who are the “deserving poor” for whom federal assistance could be considered just. As Professor Nicole Huberfield ably explains, Medicaid’s notion of the “deserving poor” meant those whose poverty could be considered “blameless” in that the condition was unavoidable.38 Professor David Orentlicher explains that Medicaid assistance was initially limited to those who “could not be labeled social deviates or paupers by choice,” and those who were made dependent through “no fault of their own.”39 Professor Sidney Watson offers this keen historical insight: the roots of this attitude lie in Elizabethan Poor Laws that informed the colonial belief that in general, poverty, disability, and illness were the result of individual moral failings.40 Under these English precursors to American welfare law, the public assumed responsibility only for the poor who were not employable, rogues, vagabonds, vagrants, or possessed of relatives who could be made responsible for their destitution, though special collective provision was made for poor soldiers, mariners, and prisoners.41 Communities were responsible for paupers within their local settlement, but not for those who were not local.42 It is no surprise, therefore, that Medicaid, even at the beginning of the program, reached only half of the nation’s indigent. From the start, what may be termed a “personal responsibility view of justice has operated in tension with the goals of egalitarian justice in competing for the soul of the Medicaid program.
III. Libertarian Justice: Medicaid Work Requirements
Philosophers do not present a single, agreed upon description of the tenants of libertarian justice. Instead, they describe the versions of the theory that are “most thoroughly worked out,”43 and those views substitute for a cohesive conceptual consensus. The libertarian perspective on justice is organized around the alleged “natural right” to “life, liberty and property.” The important premise seems to be that libertarianism protects individual liberty by protecting against unjust transfers of property generally, and most definitively prohibits governmental interference with individual liberty by the transfer property from one person to another.44 Libertarian justice does, however, make room for the state to provide for those who suffer catastrophic contingencies that are not the result of natural bad luck, but are outcomes caused by others who have worsened conditions for the poor such that they have fallen below an acceptable societal baseline condition.45 The general premise, then, is that no one should worsen the situation of others, and all should be left to live in the state that naturally occurs, absent disruption that harms others. Fredrick Hayek was a champion of libertarian justice. Hayek posited not only that egalitarian social justice was a vacuous “mirage,” but asserted it was a dangerous view that could lead to the destruction of personal freedom.46 Hayek was concerned with justice insofar as it affected how people treat one another in a market economy where all are free to use their knowledge for their own purposes.47
Applied to Medicaid, the libertarian view of justice questions whether government sponsored redistribution of resources to the poor is just, or truly in the service of the common good.48 As a policy matter, Medicaid work requirements represents an example of this view of justice because they minimize the extent to which government interferes with the property rights of non-needy individuals, by restricting transfer payments to those who are not only poor, but also unable to work. In the libertarian framework, justice is furthered by abstaining from reallocating what belongs to others, and by “doing no harm to those who do not harm.”49 Applied to the Medicaid context, work requirements serve the libertarian tradition of justice. In contrast to the egalitarian view that the justice involves ensuring equal access to the right to health care, the libertarian view favors an absolute right to avoid redistribution.50 Under the latter view, the interference of ownership title in funds must be protected from what libertarians would regard as an “unjustified coercion”—any government-sponsored effort to collect wealth and income, for reallocating to another, instead of leaving to each what belongs to him.51
On January 11, 2018, CMS issued a letter to state Medicaid directors, providing a new Guidance document, and soliciting input on Section 1115 waiver proposals that would impose work requirements (referred to as “community engagement”) in Medicaid as a condition of eligibility.52 The guidance described the potential scope of requirements that could be approved and presents the case for how these policies promote the objectives of the Medicaid program.53 This action reversed previous positions of both Democratic and Republican administrations, “which had not approved such waiver requests on the basis that such provisions would not further the program’s purposes of promoting health coverage and access.”54 The Guidance asserted that such provisions would promote program objectives by helping states “in their efforts to improve Medicaid enrollee health and well-being through incentivizing work and community engagement.”55 President Trump subsequently issued Executive Order 13828 on April 10, 2018, ordering several federal agencies to enforce existing work requirements for Medicaid and develop new work programs.56 On March 27, 2019, Judge James E. Boasberg of the Federal District Court for the District of Columbia “rejected for a second time Kentucky’s attempt to require recipients to work or volunteer as a condition of coverage and blocked a similar rule in Arkansas, which has resulted in more than 18,000 people losing coverage since last summer.”57 Nevertheless, the number of states enacting Medicaid work requirements continues to grow, in no small part due to the appeal these requirements have to the libertarian notions of justice.
Tumblr media
Figure 1. Work Requirement waivers: Approved and Pending (December 2019)58 Source: Kaiser Family Foundation
Objections to these work requirements begin with the evidence that most Medicaid recipients already work, making the requirement largely unnecessary but for its symbolic value. Some sixty-five percent of men on Medicaid are working, while fifty-six percent of women are employed.59 Enrollees who live in the South are less likely to hold jobs than those in other regions, but rates were similar in rural and urban areas across all states.60 Most Medicaid enrollees who work are working full-time for the full year, but their annual incomes are still low enough to qualify for Medicaid.61 “Not surprisingly, the more education a recipient has, the more likely they are to be employed. About half of those who did not finish high school have jobs, but nearly 70% of those with at least a bachelor's degree do.”62 In families that include nonelderly Medicaid recipients, sixty percent have at least one full time worker, fourteen percent have at least one part time worker, and only twenty-one percent of families have no workers.63 Importantly, thirty-six percent of those who do not work are ill or disabled, and an additional thirty percent are taking care of children or disabled family members.64 Thus, the actual number of Medicaid recipients who have the capacity to work but do not is negligible.
A second category of critiques of work requirements is aimed at preventing harms to specific sub-populations. For example, veterans’ groups argue those with complex health needs, chronic disabilities, and those experiencing homelessness will be harmed by work requirements.65 Similar objections are raised on behalf of rural residents,66 children, women, American Indians, Alaska Natives, and people with mental health conditions.67 These populations will lose access to medical care more quickly though they have limited ability to meet the logistical rules that accompany the requirements such as reporting work status or volunteer hours to the state.
Proponents of work requirements advocate for work requirements as a “screening” mechanism, to direct the transfer of public funds toward only those who are “truly needy.”68 They describe Medicaid as a “hand up” rather than a “hand out.” Moreover, proponents advance a deterrent argument for work requirements, that focuses on a particular view of poverty. According to economists Timothy Besley and Stephen Coate,
The deterrent argument for work requirements focuses on the origins of poverty. Are individuals poor just because they have experienced bad luck or because of choices made earlier in life? If the latter is true, then public assistance may lead individuals to make choices that increase the likelihood that they will have to draw on such support in future.69
Both the deterrent and screening arguments that favor work requirements align squarely with libertarian justice principles.70 Whatever the motivation, a total of “18,164 individuals lost coverage in 2018 due to failure to meet the work and reporting requirements, and few have regained coverage in 2019.”71 In February 2019, for example, almost 5% (10,854) of all Arkansas Works enrollees “had their cases closed for reasons other than failure to meet the work and reporting requirements.”72 When considering what justice demands of the Medicaid program, a key lesson to take-away from the work requirements debate is that a commitment to achieving justice equally motivates the opponents and proponents of Medicaid.
IV. Utilitarian Justice: Efforts and Threats to Medicaid’s Impact
Utilitarianism is the ethical tradition that holds “that action is best, which procures the greatest happiness for the greatest numbers.” Utilitarian justice aims to produce the greatest net sum of happiness for society overall.73 When applied to health care, the goal becomes achieving the maximum overall health of the population, but utilitarianism can imply several variants on the exact method to achieve the desired maximization. For example, one approach could be to prioritize improving the health of the most destitute in society in order to yield the greatest overall gain to societal well-being.74 Another approach to utilitarianism could be to express indifference towards any particular policy that benefits the health of the poor versus the rich in society, so long as the overall impact is to improve societal health generally.75 Because utilitarian goals may be achieved independent of distributional concerns, some have criticized this perspective as “the folly of a simple-minded health benefit maximization approach to health policy.”76 Nevertheless, where Medicaid is concerned, utilitarian principles may seek to maximize the cost effectiveness of delivering health care rather than the health outcomes of Medicaid beneficiaries themselves. One Medicaid demonstration project that reflects a utilitarian view of justice is called “Money Follows the Person Rebalancing Demonstration” (MFP).77
The MFP Rebalancing Demonstration Grant was authorized by the Deficit Reduction Act of 2005 to help states increase the use of home and community-based rather than institutional long- term care services. This grant makes it easier for Medicaid funds to support delivery of high quality, long-term social service needs to seniors.78 Recall that Medicaid is the nation’s primary payor for long term services and supports for millions of low-income Americans. This may include payments to nursing homes, adult daycare programs, home health aides, as well as assistance with transportation and employment.79 Approximately twenty percent of all Medicaid payments go toward long-term care.80 Therefore, the MFP program can be seen as Congress’ utilitarian effort to help states rebalance their Medicaid long-term care systems, without regard for the wealth or poverty of beneficiaries. Forty-three states and D.C. participate in the demonstration. However, it has not been permanently funded,81 and Congress has no data to evaluate the program’s effectiveness.82 This particular shortcoming in the MFP program – its lack of concrete evidence to evaluate the program’s effectiveness -is emblematic of a major reason that Medicaid is widely perceived to have fallen short of its justice goals from a utilitarian perspective.
Another primary threat to meeting utilitarian goals is the Medicaid program’s insufficient reimbursement rates. Data from a 2017 RAND survey provide an overview of the empirical literature that shows ninety percent of surveyed providers cite “low reimbursement” as a key driver in their decision to avoid or reduce their level of participation in the Medicaid program, a finding that is “consistent with related studies conducted over the past [thirty] years.”83 Other issues around reimbursement are also frequently cited as factors that discourage Medicaid participation, including “delayed reimbursement, high administrative burden associated with enrollment and billing processes, and lower reimbursements for nurse practitioners and physician assistants relative to physicians.”84 The average Medicaid payment rate for primary care services in 2012 was lower than the Medicare rate in forty-eight states and the District of Columbia and represented an average of approximately fifty-nine percent.85
A further threat grows out of Medicaid’s low reimbursement rates that affect the level of physician participation in the program, thus compromising Medicaid’s ability to reach a maximum number of potential beneficiaries.86 “In 2013, most office-based physicians (95.3%) [were accepting] new patients. The percentage of physicians accepting new Medicaid patients (68.9%) was lower than the percentage accepting new Medicare patients (83.7%) or new privately insured patients (84.7%).”87 At that time, specialists were accepting new Medicaid patients more readily than primary care physicians.88 “Physician participation in Medicaid is generally highest in the most rural states. In the 11 states where at least half the population lives in rural areas, the median Medicaid physician participation rate is 90%, compared to 71% in the 25 states where less than one-quarter of the population is rural.”89 However, the percentage of physicians accepting new Medicaid patients varied by state, ranging from thirty-nine percent in New Jersey to ninety-seven percent in Nebraska.90
Another threat to Medicaid’s ability to maximize health outcomes overall is the extent to which the program suffers from fraud and waste. In Fiscal Year 2017 alone, improper payments—which include things like payment for non-covered services or for services that were billed but not provided—totaled more than $36 billion.91 It is estimated that fifty-four percent of the improper payments were the result of states not screening or enrolling providers as they are required to do.92 (State Medicaid agencies are required to screen providers before enrolling them in the program and revalidate providers enrolled in the program every five years; the purpose of these requirements, which also apply to Medicare and CHIP, is to keep out bad actors who put beneficiaries and program funds at risk).93 Another estimated thirty-one percent of Medicaid improper payments were attributable to eligibility errors. In addition, some states have been found to engage in exploitive practices to increase federal matching funds. For example, in Pennsylvania, a state tax on Medicaid managed care plans was used to draw down an additional $1 billion over three years.94
Medicaid critics capitalize on the potential utilitarian injustice of the program. The story goes that Medicaid weakens the fabric and ethic of our overall economy by using funds to pay some for what others have to work to receive. The notion that Medicaid might be paying for people who are “gaming the system” while others work hard to succeed within the system depends on portraying the program as welfare for the exploitative. This was the meaning behind constructing the tale of the “Welfare Queen.”95 This was an effort to build a caricature (albeit built on a single real person’s story) in order to associate Medicaid with a person who combines one part sloth with two parts slick to manipulate the American government into paying for what others must work to achieve.96 These are not the people who are Medicaid recipients; once again, the data show that sixty-three percent of Medicaid enrollees work; eleven percent of those not working are ill or disabled, twelve percent are primary care-givers, and seven percent are attending school.97
Notwithstanding its shortcomings, or the perspective from which it is viewed, the Medicaid program remains the most important program in the nation in the effort to achieve health justice. The Association of State and Territorial Health Officials recently put it this way: Medicaid is uniquely positioned to enhance public health efforts as it is the largest source of coverage for low income and vulnerable individuals who experience the greatest health disparities.”98 Because of the population that it reaches and its inherent flexibility Medicaid remains the most important program in the nation’s effort to achieve health equity.
The final section of this article presents a proposal that rests on this view. It proposes that in light of the size of the Medicaid program, and its service to the precise population most affected by health inequity, the Medicaid program is ideally suited to apply its flexibility to achieve the social justice aims of public health. The next section of this article argues that Medicaid is the nation’s weapon of choice in the fight for population health equity, and thereby achieve equitable justice.
V. Equitable Justice: Medicaid and the Social Determinants of Health
The most recent and comprehensive explication of the justice aims for public health has been advanced by Madison Powers and Ruth Faden.99 Their framework recognizes justice as an “inherently remedial task” and therefore assumes no ideal distributional starting point.100 Instead, in an intensely pragmatic fashion, Powers and Faden lay out a theory of social justice that adds several important concepts required to serve the justice objectives that lie at the core of the Medicaid program.101 First, the demands of justice for low-wealth communities extend beyond ensuring access to health care alone. The injustice that causes Medicaid populations to suffer inferior health outcomes is cumulative:
[Q]uestions of justice emerge from the operation of the totality of social institutions, practices, and policies that both independently and in combination have the potential for profound and pervasive impact on human well-being in all of its essential aspects. . . . [Q]uestions about which inequalities matter most are comprehensible only by examining all of the social determinants having cumulative and interactive effects on human well-being. . . . Taken in tandem, they can reinforce and perpetuate clusters of disadvantage, and in the worst of possible scenarios, the cumulative disadvantages that emerge become nearly 102 impossible to escape or avoid without heroic effort or extraordinary good luck.
This insight is crucial to addressing the health needs of the low-wealth Medicaid population because it takes into account that eliminating unjustly poor health outcomes will require attention to those that are not attributable solely to the vectors of disease, illness, or injury.103 Second, Powers and Faden teach us that unjust inequalities are both distributive and relational:
[J]ustice is concerned with more than distributive principles. In addition, much of what justice comprehends lies beyond an assessment of each person’s distributive shares . . . . For example, worries about social subordination and stigma, lack of respect, lack of institutions, and social practices that adequately support capacities for attachment and self-determination also are matters of justice—for both individuals and groups.104
This insight is fundamental to addressing the health needs of the low-wealth Medicaid population who continue to suffer egregious racial and ethnic health and health care disparities. Subordination—that is racial and ethnic discrimination—interact through multiple social determinants of health including housing, employment, education, environmental, and criminal justice inequality—to proximately produce widely disparate health and social outcomes for minority communities.105 The Medicaid program is an appropriate mechanism to remedy this public health crisis for at least three important reasons.
First, Medicaid touches the very population that is most in need of health justice. Medicaid provides health insurance coverage to more people than any other single program in the United States, with coverage for low-income children, adults, seniors, and those with disabilities. As of March 2017, there were seventy-four million Medicaid and CHIP enrollees, of which thirty-six million were enrolled in CHIP or were children enrolled in Medicaid, according to the Centers for Medicare and Medicaid Services.106 These families are overwhelmingly poor; sixty-one percent of Medicaid’s non-elderly beneficiaries are below 100% of the Federal poverty level and eighty-three percent of enrolled children are in that low-income bracket.107
Second, the Medicaid program has the inherent flexibility that could meaningfully extend to finance social drivers of health outcomes if (and this is a very big contingency) the program were adequately funded to do so.108 Already, many states are experimenting with demonstration projects using Section 1115 waivers to fund interventions aimed at improving access to and quality of the social determinants of health for low-wealth communities. For example, CMS approved North Carolina’s “Healthy Opportunity Pilot” Section 1115 waiver in October 2018.109 The waiver provides the North Carolina Department of Health and Human Services (DHHS) authority to transition its fee-for-service delivery system to a managed care program and, as part of the transition, important flexibility to implement a groundbreaking pilot program in select regions. Through this program, the state will invest $650 million in Medicaid funding to promote value through evidence-based interventions designed to address non-medical factors that drive health outcomes and costs. “The Healthy Opportunities Pilots will provide evidence-based interventions to address housing, food, transportation, interpersonal violence and toxic stress for Medicaid-enrolled pregnant women, children and adults who meet certain eligibility criteria.”110 Healthy Opportunity Pilot participants must have at least one physical or behavioral health risk factor (e.g., multiple chronic conditions or history of a poor birth outcome) and at least one social risk factor (e.g., homelessness/housing insecurity or food insecurity)—as defined by DHHS. Each pilot must address all domains of need (housing, food, transportation, interpersonal violence and toxic stress) for all types of eligible beneficiaries (pregnant women, children and adults).111
In another example of Medicaid’s flexibility, Louisiana’s Department of Health partnered with the state’s Housing Authority to braid funding in a Permanent Supportive Housing (PSH) program for disabled populations. These funds included Community Development Block Grant, disaster recovery funds, Federal Rental Assistance (e.g., Housing Choice Vouchers, Section 811 Project Rental Assistance), and Low-Income Housing Tax Credits.112 The Louisiana PSH program links affordable rental housing with voluntary, flexible, and individualized services to people with severe and complex disabilities, enabling them to live successfully in the community. After Hurricanes Katrina and Rita, advocates for both people with disabilities and homeless people, along with consumers, service providers, with state/local governmental agencies formed a successful partnership that resulted in the development of over 3,000 units of permanent supportive housing for extremely low income people with disabilities.113
Preliminary data from the Louisiana Department of Health shows the PSH program is getting results. PSH participants’ emergency department usage is down by almost twenty-five percent, and overall hospitalizations are down.114 In an independent study for the years 2011–2012, PSH saw a twenty-four percent reduction in Medicaid costs for housed beneficiaries and ninety-five percent of those who were previously homeless have remained housed since the program’s inception.115 Finally, the principles of equitable justice that are central to the Medicaid program demand that our society eradicate avoidable, non-clinically supportable racial, ethnic, and socioeconomic health disparities; this can only be done by embracing the cumulative, interactive, distributional, and relational aspects of health inequality in America. Louisiana and North Carolina are two examples that this approach is both possible and effective.
VI. Conclusion
The struggle for the soul of Medicaid is not a recent story. But although some politicians and providers and payors may have struggled to identify the soul of the Medicaid program, the American public has not. For those who paid attention, the struggle for the soul of Medicaid was most recently and resoundingly won during the “Repeal and Replace” battle of 2017. Before Congress attempted over fifty times to eliminate the Medicaid expansion.116 Still, seven in ten (71%) Americans said they preferred “keeping Medicaid largely as it is” while fewer (26%) supported changing Medicaid to limit federal spending and increase state flexibility with regard to eligibility and services covered under the program.117 Despite the fact that most Americans favor placing conditions on Medicaid eligibility, the majority of those polled “support allowing states to impose work requirements for non-disabled adults (70 percent) and to require drug-testing (64 percent) for Medicaid beneficiaries.”118 Fewer support changes that are directed at restricting Medicaid for vulnerable populations like “stopping federal payments to Planned Parenthood for one year (30 percent), or limiting federal funding for Medicaid coverage of long-term care for seniors and people with disabilities (21 percent).”119 Medicaid critics capitalize on the assumption that poverty—without some other accompanying tragedy—is a status that no one in America endures unless they do so by choice. In this article, I have argued this view is not only incorrect, but also a fundamental contradiction of the demands of fairness and equity – that version of justice that was the very soul of Medicaid in 1965, and remains so today.
Footnotes
1 Charlene Galarneau, Getting King's Words Right, 29 J. HEALTH CARE FOR POOR & UNDERSERVED 5, 5 (2018).
2 Angela P. Harris & Aysha Pamukcu, The Civil Rights of Health: A New Approach to Challenging Structural Inequality, UCLA L. REV. (forthcoming 2019) (manuscript at 3) (on file with SSRN).
3 Nichole Huberfeld, Federalizing Medicaid, 14 U. PA. J. CONST. L. 431, 444–45 (2011). 3
4 Id. at 436.
5 Wilbur J. Cohen, Reflections on the Enactment of Medicare and Medicaid, HEALTH CARE FINANCING REV., 1985 supp., at 3, 9–10.
6 Id. at 9.
7 Rosemary Stevens & Robert Stevens, Medicaid: Anatomy of a Dilemma, 35 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 348, 348 (1970).
8 Id. at 349–50.
9 Id. at 349.
10 Robin Rudowitz et al., 10 Things to Know About Medicaid: Setting the Facts Straight, KAISER FAM. FOUND. 8, 11 (2019), http://files.kff.org/attachment/Issue-Brief-10-Things-to-Know-about-Medicaid-Setting-the-Facts-Straight.
11 See generally JOSH LEVIN, THE QUEEN: THE FORGOTTEN LIFE BEHIND AN AMERICAN MYTH (1st ed. 2019).
12 John Kitzhaber & Bruce Goldberg, A Better Way to Contain Medicaid Costs, MILBANK: THE MILBANK BLOG (June 13, 2019), http://www.milbank.org/2019/06/a-better-way-to-contain-Medicaid-costs/.
13 Id.
14 Michael McCarthy, US Republican Attempt to Repeal and Replace Affordable Care Act Collapses, BMJ (July 19, 2017), https://www.bmj.com/content/358/bmj.j3508.
15 Rudowitz et al., supra note 10, at 10.
16 Ashley Kirzinger et al., Kaiser Health Tracking Poll: Future Directions for the ACA and Medicaid, KAISER FAM. FOUND. (Feb. 24, 2017), https://www.kff.org/health-reform/poll-finding/kaiser-health-tracking-poll-future- directions-for-the-aca-and-medicaid/.
17 Id.
18 See generally Karen Dillon, ‘Medicaid 23’ Protesters’ Mass Trial Gets Under Way, PITCH (Aug. 15, 2016), https://www.thepitchkc.com/medicaid-23-protesters-trial-starts/.
19 Judith D. Moore & David G. Smith, Legislating Medicaid: Considering Medicaid and Its Origins, HEALTH CARE FINANCING REV., Winter 2005, at 45, 45.
20 Id.
21 Id.
22 Id. at 46.
23 Rudowitz et al., supra note 10, at 1.
24 Alan Weil, There’s Something About Medicaid, HEALTH AFF., Jan.–Feb. 2003, at 13, 16.
25 Id. at 14–15.
26 See John Holahan et al., Explaining the Recent Growth in Medicaid Spending, HEALTH AFF., Fall 1993, at 177, 177, 183–85.
27 See Moore & Smith, supra note 19, at 45.
28 Id. at 49.
29 Rudowitz et al., supra note 10, at 2.
30 Brian O. Burwell & Marilyn P. Rymer, Trends in Medicaid Eligibility: 1975 to 1985, HEALTH AFF., Winter 1987, at 30, 31–33.
31 See generally id. at 30.
32 Edward Berkowitz, Medicare and Medicaid: The Past as Prologue, HEALTH CARE FINANCING REV., Spring 2008, at 81, 82.
33 Cohen, supra note 5, at 4.
34 Id.
35 Id.
36 Arnold S. Relman, The New Medical-Industrial Complex, 303 NEW ENG. J. MED. 963, 963–70 (1980). See also, Skidmore, M. J. (1989). Ronald Reagan and “Operation Coffeecup”: a hidden episode in American political history. Journal of American culture, 12(3), 89-96.
37 Cohen, supra note 5, at 4.
38 Nicole Huberfeld & Jessica L. Roberts, Health Care and the Myth of Self-Reliance, 57 BOS. C. L. REV. 1, 12 (2016).
39 David Orentlicher, Medicaid at 50: No Longer Limited to the “Deserving” Poor?, 15 YALE J. HEALTH POL’Y L. & ETHICS 185, 185–86 (2015).
40 Sidney D. Watson, From Almshouses to Nursing Homes and Community Care: Lessons from Medicaid’s History, 26 GA. ST. U. L. REV. 937, 940 (2010).
41 Jacobus tenBroek, California’s Dual System of Family Law: Its Origin, Development, and Present Status: Part I, 16 STAN. L. REV. 257, 259 (1964).
42 Id. at 263.
43 Robert Elliot, Future Generations, Locke's Proviso and Libertarian Justice, 3 J. APPLIED PHIL. 217, 217 (1986).
44 Carl Watner, The Proprietary Theory of Justice in the Libertarian Tradition, 6 J. LIBERTARIAN STUD. 289, 289–90 (1982).
45 Elliot, supra note 43, at 220.
46 2 FRIEDRICH A. HAYEK, LAW, LEGISLATION AND LIBERTY, THE MIRAGE OF SOCIAL JUSTICE 97–99 (1976).
47 See Andrew Lister, The ‘Mirage’ of Social Justice: Hayek Against (and for) Rawls 9 (Ctr. for the Study of Soc. Justice: Dep’t of Politics & Int’l Relations, Univ. of Oxford, Working Paper No. SJ017, 2011).
48 HAYEK, supra note 46, at 2.
49 Watner, supra note 44, at 290.
50 See id. at 293.
51 Libertarianism, STAN. ENCYCLOPEDIA PHIL. (2019), https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/libertarianism.
52 See generally Ctr. for Medicare & Medicaid Servs., Opinion Letter on Opportunities to Promote Work and Community Engagement Among Medicaid Beneficiaries (Jan. 11, 2018).
53 Id.
54 Elizabeth Hinton et al., Section 1115 Medicaid Demonstration Waivers: The Current Landscape of Approved and Pending Waivers, KAISER FAM. FOUND. 2 (Feb. 12, 2019), http://files.kff.org/attachment/Issue-Brief-Section-1115- Medicaid-Demonstration-Waivers-The-Current-Landscape-of-Approved-and-Pending-Waivers.
55 Ctr. for Medicare & Medicaid Servs., supra note 52.
56 Exec. Order No. 13,828, 83 Fed. Reg. 72, 15941–15944 (Apr. 10, 2018).
57 Abby Goodnough, Judge Blocks Medicaid Work Requirements in Arkansas and Kentucky, N.Y. TIMES (Mar. 27, 2019), https://www.nytimes.com/2019/03/27/health/medicaid-work-requirement.html.
58 Medicaid Waiver Tracker: Approved and Pending Section 1115 Waivers by State, KAISER FAM. FOUND. (Jan. 16, 2020), https://www.kff.org/medicaid/issue-brief/medicaid-waiver-tracker-approved-and-pending-section-1115-waivers-by-state/.
59 Tami Luhby, Millions of Medicaid Recipients Already Work, CNN (Jan. 10, 2018), https://money.cnn.com/2018/01/10/news/economy/medicaid-work-requirement/index.html.
60 Id.
61 Id.
62 Id.
63 Rachel Garfield et al., Understanding the Intersection of Medicaid and Work, KAISER FAM. FOUND. 2 (2018), http://files.kff.org/attachment/Issue-Brief-Understanding-the-Intersection-of-Medicaid-and-Work.
64 Id. at 4 fig.
65 Taking Away Medicaid for Not Meeting Work Requirements Harms Veterans, CTR. ON BUDGET & POL'Y PRIORITIES 1–2 (2019), https://www.cbpp.org/sites/default/files/atoms/files/11-8-18-health.pdf.
66 See Taking Away Medicaid for Not Meeting Work Requirements Harms Rural Residents and Communities, CTR. ON BUDGET & POL'Y PRIORITIES 1 (2019), https://www.cbpp.org/sites/default/files/atoms/files/8-22-18health.pdf.
67 See generally Medicaid Briefs: Who Is Harmed by Work Requirements?, CTR. ON BUDGET & POL'Y PRIORITIES (2019), https://www.cbpp.org/medicaid-briefs-who-is-harmed-by-work-requirements. E.g., Taking Away Medicaid for Not Meeting Work Requirements Harms Children, CTR. ON BUDGET & POL'Y PRIORITIES 1 (2019), https://www.cbpp.org/sites/default/files/atoms/files/4-4-18health.pdf.
68 Timothy Besley & Stephen Coate, Workfare Versus Welfare: Incentive Arguments for Work Requirements in Poverty-Alleviation Programs, 82 AM. ECON. REV. 249, 249 (1992).
69 Id. at 250.
70 See id.
71 Robin Rudowitz et al., February State Data for Medicaid Work Requirements in Arkansas, KAISER FAM. FOUND. 1 (2019), http://files.kff.org/attachment/State-Data-for-Medicaid-Work-Requirements-in-Arkansas.
72 Id. at 2.
73 JULIA DRIVER, The History of Utilitarianism, STAN. ENCYCLOPEDIA PHIL. (2014), https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/utilitarianism-history/.
74 Fabienne Peter, Health Equity and Social Justice, 18 J. APPLIED PHIL. 159, 163 (2001).
75 Id. at 162.
76 MADISON POWERS & RUTH FADEN, SOCIAL JUSTICE: THE MORAL FOUNDATIONS OF PUBLIC HEALTH AND HEALTH POLICY 6 (2006).
77 See CTRS. FOR MEDICARE & MEDICAID SERVS., Money Follows the Person, MEDICAID.GOV, https://www.medicaid.gov/medicaid/long-term-services-supports/money-follows-person/index.html.
78 ERIC D. HARGAN, ACTING SEC’Y OF THE DEP’T OF HEALTH & HUMAN SERVS., REPORT TO THE PRESIDENT AND CONGRESS: THE MONEY FOLLOWS THE PERSON (MFP) REBALANCING DEMONSTRATION 2 (2017).
79 ERICA L. REAVES & MARYBETH MUSUMECI, MEDICAID AND LONG-TERM SERVICES AND SUPPORTS: A PRIMER 1 (2015).
80 Megan Thielking, Trump Wants to Cut $800 Billion from Medicaid. Where Does all the Program’s Money Go?, STAT NEWS (May 22, 2017), https://www.statnews.com/2017/05/22/medicaid-spending-breakdown/.
81 HARGAN, supra note 78. The MFP Project was first authorized by the Deficit Reduction Act of 2005 and was extended through Fiscal Year 2016 by the Affordable Care Act, although some states were able to continue to use their existing grant funds through 2020. Id. at 1. On January 24, 2019, Congress signed the Medicaid Extenders Act of 2019 into law, extending funding for MFP project for an additional three months ($112 million). Medicaid Extenders Act of 2019, Pub. L. No. 116-3, 133 Stat. 6 (2019). On March 26, 2019, the House unanimously passed H.R. 1839, the Medicaid Services Investment and Accountability Act of 2019, which would add additional short- term funding to the MFP program to fully fund it through September 2019 and would extend the expiring spousal impoverishment protections for people receiving HCBS through September 2019. Medicaid Services Investment and Accountability Act of 2019, Pub. L. No. 116-16, 144 Stat. 852 (2019). Another bill, the EMPOWER Care Act, has also been introduced and would reauthorize MFP for five years. H.R. 1342, 116th Cong. (1st Sess. 2019); S.B. 548, 116th Cong. (1st Sess. 2019).
82 HARGAN, supra note 78, at 19–27.
83 JUSTIN W. TIMBIE ET AL., EXAMINING THE IMPLEMENTATION OF THE MEDICAID PRIMARY CARE PAYMENT INCREASE 1 (2017).
84 Id.
85 Stephen Zuckerman et al., How Much Will Medicaid Physician Fees for Primary Care Rise in 2013? Evidence from a 2012 Survey of Medicaid Physician Fees, KAISER FAM. FOUND. 2, 8 (2012), https://www.kff.org/wp- content/uploads/2013/01/8398.pdf.
86 See David Baugh & Shinu Verghese, Physician Service Use and Participation in Medicaid, 2009, MATHEMATICA 1, 9 (2012), https://www.cms.gov/Research-Statistics-Data-and-Systems/Computer-Data-and-Systems/MedicaidDataSourcesGenInfo/Downloads/MAX_IB11_PhysicianParticipation.pdf.
87 Esther Hing et al., Acceptance of New Patients with Public and Private Insurance by Office-based Physicians: United States, 2013, CTRS. FOR DISEASE CONTROL & PREVENTION 6 (2015), https://www.cdc.gov/nchs/data/databriefs/db195.pdf.
88 Sandra L. Decker, Two-Thirds of Primary Care Physicians Accepted New Medicaid Patients in 2011-12: A Baseline to Measure Future Acceptance Rates, 32 HEALTH AFF. 1183, 1185 (2013).
89 Julia Paradise, Data Note: A Large Majority of Physicians Participate in Medicaid, KAISER FAM. FOUND. 1 (2017), http://files.kff.org/attachment/Data-Note-A-Large-Majority-of-Physicians-Participate-in-Medicaid.
90 Id. at 1.
91 Andy Schneider, How to Reduce Improper Payments in Medicaid, GEO. U. HEALTH POL’Y INST. (Apr. 19, 2018), https://ccf.georgetown.edu/2018/04/19/measuring-medicaids-mistakes-estimating-improper-payments/.
92 Id.
93 Id.
94 DANIEL R. LEVINSON, DEP’T OF HEALTH & HUMAN SERVS., PENNSYLVANIA’S GROSS RECEIPTS TAX ON MEDICAID MANAGED CARE ORGANIZATIONS APPEARS TO BE AN IMPERMISSIBLE HEALTH-CARE-RELATED TAX 9 (2014).
95 See ‘Welfare Queen’ Becomes Issue in Reagan Campaign, N.Y. TIMES (Feb. 15, 1976), https://www.nytimes.com/1976/02/15/archives/welfare-queen-becomes-issue-in-reagan-campaign-hitting-a-nerve- now.html.
96 Id.
97 See Garfield et al., supra note 63.
98 Noelle Andrade & Emily Moore, Maximizing Medicaid-Public Health Partnerships, ASTHO (Sept. 14, 2016), https://www.astho.org/StatePublicHealth/Maximizing-Medicaid-Public-Health-Partnerships/9-14-16/.
99 See generally POWERS & FADEN, supra note 76.
100 See id. at 5.
101 See generally id. at 15–29.
102 Id. at 5.
103 Id. at 16–29. In fact, Powers and Faden advance a theory of justice that encompasses six essential and required features of well-being: health, personal security, reasoning, respect, attachment, and self-determination. POWERS & FADEN, supra note 76, at 6.
104 Id. at 6.
105 See generally Dayna Bowen Matthew, Structural Inequality: The Greatest Threat to America’s Health and How the Affordable Care Act Can Help, GEO. L.J. (forthcoming 2020) (on file with author).
106 State Health Facts Data: Monthly Child Enrollment in Medicaid and CHIP, KAISER FAM. FOUND. (March 2017), https://www.kff.org/medicaid/state-indicator/total-medicaid-and-chip-child- enrollment/?currentTimeframe=30&selectedRows=%7B%22wrapups%22:%7B%22united- states%22:%7B%7D%7D%7D&sortModel=%7B%22colId%22:%22Location%22,%22sort%22:%22asc%22%7D.
107 Rudowitz et al., supra note 10, at 4 fig.
108 E.g., Karen DeSalvo & Michael O. Leavitt, For an Option to Address Social Determinants of Health, Look to Medicaid, HEALTH AFF. (July 8, 2019), https://www.healthaffairs.org/do/10.1377/hblog20190701.764626/full/.
109 See Proposed Program Design: Section 1115 Demonstration Waiver, N.C. DEP’T HEALTH & HUM. SERV., https://www.ncdhhs.gov/assistance/medicaid-transformation/proposed-program-design (last visited Jan. 19, 2020).
110 N.C. DEP’T OF HEALTH & HUMAN SERVS., HEALTHY OPPORTUNITIES PILOTS FACT SHEET 1, 3 (2018).
111 Id. at 3.
112 AMY CLARY & TINA KARTIKA, NAT’L ACAD. FOR STATE HEALTH POLICY, BRAIDING FUNDS TO HOUSE COMPLEX MEDICAID BENEFICIARIES: KEY POLICY LESSONS FROM LOUISIANA 1 (2017); LA. DEP’T OF HEALTH & HOSPS., LOUISIANA’S PERMANENT SUPPORTIVE HOUSING PROGRAM: A PARTNERSHIP BETWEEN THE DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH AND HOSPITALS AND THE LOUISIANA HOUSING CORPORATION 1 (2014).
113 Permanent Supportive Housing (PSH), LA. DEP’T HEALTH, http://ldh.la.gov/index.cfm/page/1732 (last visited Jan. 18, 2020).
114 CTR. FOR HEALTH CARE STRATEGIES, INC., LINKING HOUSING AND HEALTH FOR SUSTAINABLE CROSS-DISABILITY SERVICE DELIVERY: LOUISIANA POST-KATRINA AND RITA 5 (2018).
115 Id.
116 Tessa Berenson, Reminder: The House Voted to Repeal Obamacare More than 50 Times, TIME (Mar. 24, 2017), https://time.com/4712725/ahca-house-repeal-votes-obamacare/.
117 Data Note: 10 Charts About Public Opinion on Medicaid, KAISER FAM. FOUND. (June 27, 2017), https://www.kff.org/medicaid/poll-finding/data-note-10-charts-about-public-opinion-on-medicaid/.
118 Id.
119 Id.
0 notes
uniteordie-usa · 7 years
Text
Why Increased Consciousness is the Only Path Forward | Michael Krieger
http://uniteordiemedia.com/why-increased-consciousness-is-the-only-path-forward-michael-krieger/ https://uniteordiemedia.com/wp-content/uploads/2017/07/yoda-UniteOrDie-1-600x253.jpg Why Increased Consciousness is the Only Path Forward | Michael Krieger Today’s post will be the fifth and final article this week exploring how a human consciousness development model known as Spiral Dynamics can help us understand the increasingly insane world around us, as well as chart a path forward. To fully grasp the concepts in today’s piece, you should...
Today’s post will be the fifth and final article this week exploring how a human consciousness development model known as Spiral Dynamics can help us understand the increasingly insane world around us, as well as chart a path forward. To fully grasp the concepts in today’s piece, you should read the prior four articles. I know it’s a lot to ask, but I wouldn’t have dedicated my entire first week back from a break to this stuff if I didn’t think it was of the utmost importance.
Lost in the Political Wilderness
What is Spiral Dynamics and Why Have I Become So Interested in It?
How a Breakdown in Liberal Ideology Created Trump – Part 1
How a Breakdown in Liberal Ideology Created Trump – Part 2
We’ve all heard variations of the famous quote by Joseph de Maistre that: “Every nation gets the government it deserves.” I’ve spent the last decade or so rejecting this. After all, it’s hard for someone who has dedicated his life to flushing out the severe societal problems we face to accept that this is our destiny.
Fortunately, the framework of Spiral Dynamics has helped me see the truth in this observation, at least when it comes to America, where we have far more avenues for liberty than more autocratic nations. According to Ken Wilber in his recent e-book, Trump and a Post-Truth World: An Evolutionary Self-Correction, America’s descent into a parasitic, unhealthy, increasingly authoritarian society is a function of traffic jam in the evolution of consciousness that occurred due to the total failure of green level thinking to develop many of the initially positive realizations that sprung up in the 1960’s. As Wilber explains:
One of the paradoxical reasons that it is so important that our culture at large understand the general basics of a developmental view is that such an understanding would allow people to see the general limits of just how much they will be able to agree with each other in the first place.  All “1st- tier” stages (crimson, magenta, red, amber, orange, and green), as we saw, think that their truth and values are the only genuinely real and important truth and values. That is not likely to ever change fundamentally (it hasn’t for the last hundred-thousand years that it’s been in existence). But the degree to which those beliefs are held, and the aggression that is invested in such a belief, can indeed be softened, opened, dosed with a bit of kindness and compassion—and the example for this must come from the leading-edge. That’s one of the things that a leading-edge does—while being the “highest” level of evolution at that point, it leads all levels—it provides a direction that can energize the population at large—and failing that, it simply fails to lead. But that is exactly one of the problems that the collapse of green ended up generating—all other values were not met with an open compassion but were aggressively “deconstructed” and decommissioned and tossed in the “basket of deplorables,” and anyone who continued to believe them was subjected to harsh, vocal, and unrelenting ridicule. The “culture wars” (which, by the way, are exactly the battle between amber, orange, and green—between traditional mythic religion, modern science and business, and postmodern multiculturalism) —but the culture wars, under green “leadership,” went nuclear. What green was teaching this culture, by example, were sophisticated ways to despise (and deconstruct) those who disagreed with you—they aren’t just wrong, they are the source of every major force of oppression, injustice, slavery, and worse. You do not want to embrace them with kindness and understanding, you literally want to deconstruct them (while you yourself ounder in aperspectival madness, cackling loudly with each new victory helping move others to an equal infestation by aperspectival insanity). What so desperately needs to be understood, from a developmental and evolutionary perspective, is that each major stage of development becomes a possible station in life for those who stop there, and there is nothing that can be done about that—except make sure that all the means of further development are made as widely available as possible (a core task of the leading-edge), and—just as importantly—making room in the society for individuals who are at each station of life (red, amber, orange, green, or integral), and douse the whole affair with outrageous amounts of loving kindness—and do so by example.  
Green hasn’t been doing so by example, as everyone knows by now, and based on some of the recent insane outbursts of violence at Berkeley, for instance, I’m not particularly optimistic that green will get it’s act together and lead the way forward. As such, I gravitative towards Wilber’s second possible resolution to the problem, if we are to move forward.
The one other option, slightly different, is for evolution to leap-frog to an integral stage of unfolding as its new leading-edge, which would inherently perform all of the tasks now required of a regenerated green. This “leap- frogging” would not constitute skipping a stage (which is not possible), but it would mean building a higher stage on a diseased predecessor, which lands it with a handicap right from the start. The integral attitude, however, is designed to effectively spot and route around such roadblocks, and this we would expect to see.
The most likely course of action, however, is some mixture of both. That’s not a cop-out, it’s a precise prediction. Green simply cannot function, not even on its own level, if it continues in its extreme, mean-green-meme (vindictively seeing “deplorables” everywhere), hyper-sensitive, over-the- top politically correct, dysfunctional, and pathological form in which it now exists. Its inherent contradictions are increasingly being seen and felt, and ways to work around them are being explored (which incorporate the partial truths of green but not their extreme and pathological absolutisms).
That lessening of green’s pervasive hostility and vindictiveness toward all previous stages of development is what we identied as “step one” in the requisite self-healing of green. There is at least a decent likelihood that this will—and to some degree already has—begun to happen. On the other hand, “step two”—the realization that growth holarchies provide the actual basis of the value judgments that green is already making, and that these growth holarchies also are the only truly effective means to displace the dominator hierarchies that green correctly ranks on the bottom of the list of social desirables—is a bit less likely to occur at the green level itself, but will most likely depend upon the transformation to integral 2nd tier. My strong suspicion, therefore, is that green will perform a good deal of step one on its own, and that this will have a very positive effect on culture at large. (And conversely, to the extent that at least this first step is not taken, then the self-corrective drive of evolution will continue to push, and push, and push into existing affairs, driving more Trump-like “disasters” as evolution redoubles its efforts to force its way through these recalcitrant obstructions.)
But step two will likely be taken at this time only by integral communities themselves, and otherwise will await the growth of 10 percent of the population which would initiate a tipping point and propel the integral stage into being the next-higher leading-edge, with altogether stunning repercussions.
Contributing to this growth and increase in truly inclusive awareness, and under the drive to discover “what’s next” after postmodernism, various Integral theories and metatheories are increasingly gaining ground, and wherever they do, they automatically correct the green dysfunctions that they unearth. Little by little, in other words, an Integral awareness is helping to embody an evolutionary self-correction in its very actions.
It is this Integral view that I wish to recommend to any who are ready for such…In embracing all of yesterday, it opens us to all of tomorrow. And it will provide a leading-edge of evolution the likes of which humanity has literally never seen before.
This is indeed the next, authentic and genuine leading-edge, and it has already begun its inevitable emergence. It carries with it the inexorable drive to “transcend and include” literally all of the previous stages of development and the stations of life that they now inhabit—but minus the inherent rancor that each of them, on its own, feels for the others. Humankind has never had a leading-edge like this at any previous point in history. It is indeed “cataclysmic,” “a monumental leap in meaning,” and it is here for each of us to embrace and express should we so desire. And it is the one, sure, and certain balm—if authentically inhabited—for the isolating, regressive, repressive, mean-spirited, and fragmenting state in which the world now nds itself rapidly drowning.
This week’s series of posts aren’t meant to speak to everybody. These five pieces were written because the Spiral Dynamics model initiated me into a powerful framework that spoke to me on a very deep level and provided me with incredible understanding. As such, I felt the concept would resonate equally powerfully with a minority of you, and based on the response so far, this has definitely been the case…..
  Read More: libertyblitzkrieg.com/2017/02/10/why-increased-consciousness-is-the-only-path-forward/
0 notes
school-bleh · 7 years
Text
Native Americans, Research Task
The culture of Native Americans past, present, and future.
 The Spirituality and values of the Iñupiat peoples of North Alaska
The Iñupiat peoples are native to northern Americas. Their traditional territories spanned from Bearing Sea to the Canada-United States border, however now they are only affiliated with northern and northwest Alaska. Iñupiat meaning ‘real people’ were once a hunter gather nation relying heavily on marine animals like whales, seals, walrus and fishes, as well as seasonal wildlife like caribou, birds, rabbits, and even cautiously polar bears. But it was not what they hunted but their ideology about hunting and the natural world that makes Iñupiat’s so impressive. Hunting is an important part of their life, because it was survival, not of an individual or family but of a community. The idea of sharing is what keep the communities alive “we just give, that’s who we are” explains cultural ambassador Frantz (Tiġitquuraq) Brower (2016). If Iñupiat nations did not share, it would be near impossible to live in such a harsh climate. This survival and their relationship to the natural world that keeps them alive in one of the harshest and most unforgiving places on earth is what defines their perspective and values. The Alaskan predictably of survival is directly tied to the harsh environment around them, through this the Iñupiat peoples can better understand and respect their environment as it is their lifeline. They spend all their time in nature, developing an intimate relationship with it that is often lost in our modern world. Living this lifestyle gives Iñupiats the belief that everything has a spirit, was alive in its own way and deserved respect, from the animals they kill, to the water they fish from, to the ice they hunt on, and the tundra they pick berries from. Everything is equally important, there is no hierarchy. Respecting the animal, and the land is the true meaning of success to the Iñupiats. An example of the compassion the Iñupiat maintain, is when a young man accidently killed a mother polar bear. “A boy of 9 was out seal hunting, when he was attacked from behind, he grabbed his knife and saved himself only to realise he just killed a mother polar bear. Traditionally we always avoid killing mothers, as we see it as our sacred duty to protect them. The boy then had to present himself to the council, and the elders decided that he must mother the now orphaned young. And so he looked after it, and then eventually taught it to survive in the wild on its own.” Shares Fannie (Kuutuuq) Akpik on a storey from her childhood. The simplicity of living equally in line with nature is inspiring and should be more recognised as an important aspect in our modern society.
  The Government of the Incan Empire
The Inca were a rling faction who controlled a large empire that stretched along the Pacific coast from Ecuador to northern Chile. This empire; the Inca dynasty began in 1200 A.D. and lasted until the 16th century, when the Spanish Conquerors arrived. The Inca Empire was likely one of the biggest empires of all the indigenous Americas before Spanish arrival, owing to its estimated population of 10-12 million. The Inca Empire was especially exceptional because of the complexity of its political organizations, engineering feats, and built structures, in the almost inaccessible location of the Andes mountains, unequal to any other organization of Native American people. What remains of this civilization is scattered over the highlands of the Andes, remaining cities, and buildings depict how impressive and established the society once was. The Inca’s rapid expanse over Peruvian land is made possible by its stable and controlling form of government in opposition to little competition, isolation, and local conflict. This government is held together through the martial alliances formed to solidify political relations. The emperor of the Inca would marry daughters of prestigious local lords to retain peace in the community, while lesser rulers would form powers around major cities, by intermarriage to create a local alliances and kinships that many other regions in south America lacked at the time. Another reason for the Incas success is their military power. Professor Terence D'Altroy (American Archaeology Institute) believes that “contributing to the Inca advancement was that conflict had long been honed as a requisite for leadership, so that militarism was built into the culture.” As consequence to this the strongest most able person normally held a lot of power in a society like this, which can be effective in expanding power, but destructive in stability leading to possible factional competition and break down of political structure. Incan society was strictly organised from the emperor and royal family down to the peasants. The emperor himself was thought to have been a direct descendent to the sun god, therefore ruled with divine authority except for the influence of revolt, and traditions. Below the emperor was the aristocracy which encompassed descendants of the emperor and his relations. These Incas held important government, religious, and military roles. The empire itself was named Tahuantinsuyu, meaning “Land of the Four Quarters”, with Cusco the capital in the centre. A blood relative of the emperor served as governor over each quarter, then officials would further divide the area into progressively smaller and more manageable units, each governor oversaw ten district governs whom ruled another leader in charge of small villages, who then oversaw foremen supervising peasants. At times native populations were uprooted and resettled in other areas, for resource, and politically motivated reasons. Furthermore these relocations continued the spread of the empire, their ideas, culture, and unity of the Incan empire.
 The Warfare of the Lakota Tribe
The Lakota Native Americans inhabited a large portion of the Great Plains. The heartland of this country was a vast sea of grass, mountainous terrain and forested rivers running up against the western wall of the Plains, the Rocky Mountains. The Lakota are a fiercely strong tribe, who’s notable leaders include; Red Claw, Red Horn Buffalo, Black Elk, and Crazy Horse. When the Lakota travelled to the Arkansas’ hot springs they were joined with other tribes, so that they could hunt, trade, and take the healing waters together. Even when opposing tribes were at war, individuals would come here together in safety and peace. The connection and respect for nature and each other that the Great Plains Native Americans have, can clearly be seen here. Despite this show of peace seasonal warfare was constant in the area surrounding the Great Lakes, as tribes were being driven out, displaced, and resettled conflict was inevitable. When the horses arrived in the Great Plains it completely changed the way Lakota people lived and hunted. Suddenly food supply was not a problem as hunting buffalo from horseback was much more efficient and safer. This gave them more confidence with fewer restraints and true nomadism began in North America. The horse-rich tribes shared roaming and hunting territories in the Plains, and even shared cultural traditions and military alliances purely on the existence of a common enemy. The Lakota tribe prospered at this, and gained more goods and equipment to ride into battle with like small shields painted with godly symbols, like medicine bears and birds to protect them from the enemy. Bows gained greater power, and clubs and lances were used in close combat. Rifles were not usually used due to lack of access western parts and efficiency issues. Honour in warfare was received to the Lakota tribes through a “Coup”. It signified bravery, and status within a tribe. Striking the opponent with a gun or bow, can be considered a higher achievement than actually killing him. In the early days the Lakota would rise in vast numbers against opponents with nothing but sticks or bare hands. They would hit their enemy make sure to never kill them, and ride away. This was done because in the Lakota’s believed that killing enemies was unnecessary, and that real bravery is without violence. Honours were usually granted for stealing horses, riding down an enemy, stealing weapons, or scalping him. the coups came in the forms of insignia like, special feathers, markings on horses, beads, pictographs, etc. The different perspectives on warfare as a more respectful and honourable act is important to remember in the Modern World. The Lakota people are fierce, but fight with strength and honour. Making warfare less like a butchering and more of a ritual of leaning and becoming strong as a nation.
  Source Analysis
Source1; “The Inupiat people are a living people, and a living culture. Even though we live in northern Alaska, which covers the mast area from Nome, all the way to the Canadian border, is that there’s this extreme value of interconnectedness and independence. It’s a hunting society, It’s a gathering society, from thousands of years. This is what creates our culture. That special relationship between humans, and the natural world, and the animals, and that it teaches you how to have a society that doesn’t do too much harm to the world. Love and respect: for nature, for one another, for elders, a very, very fundamental value, key to life. Our values are something that bind us all: The importance of sharing with another. The importance of spirituality and the connection to the land, our traditions, how we hunt, sharing of stories and songs and dances. It’s very important to me its who I am as a person. We are very proud of who we are and want to continue that.”- Cultural Ambassadors for the Inupiat people (2015) A Living People, A Living Culture. Never Alone Cultural Insights.
Source 1: An interview about the culture and people of the Inupiat tribe of Northern Alaska. It is a primary source as the people being interviewed are genuine Iñupiat people, practicing their same living culture that hasn’t changed in hundreds of years. The perspective of the interview is from the Iñupiat people themselves, the motive being to show that Iñupiat people and their culture as a living tradition that’s being practiced not just an object to be viewed in a museum. It highlights the Native Alaskan tribe in a positive light, explaining the good values and connectedness the community feels together from their perspective. It is very useful when studying the Iñupiat tribes despite it being only from their perspective because it explains what their culture is from their point of view without degrading any other bias. It shows the importance the people feel about who they are and how they want it to be equally respected. The purpose positions the audience to think about Iñupiat spirituality from an indigenous point of view. Its Usefulness is not limited as the interview investigates lots of aspects about the Iñupiat culture and the extent of its significance to themselves. It does not require cross-referencing and is both relevant and reliable even with its positive bias.
  Source 2: Is the lost city of Machu Picchu, only discovered by the west in the 20th century. It’s believed to have been a private estate for an Incan emperor. It is a primary source built by the Incan Empire in 1450, but was abandoned a century later when the Spanish conquest arrived. As there is little information other than what buildings still stand there today the Machu Picchu as impressive as it is cannot tell us a lot about the people or the society that lived there at the time. However it does have different buildings in areas inside the estate like a temple for religious purposes, an agricultural sector for farming, and an urban sector for living, so it can tell us some information about the way people lived here. It shows the skill and manpower the empire must have had to construct such an impressive engineering feat in the 15th century in such a difficult environment. The source also showcases the different standards of living as the different sections differ in quality and luxury of housing and objects. So it is useful to some extent. However with everything that it tell us we can never truly know for use if that’s the true, so more evidence and other sources would be needed to back of the credibility of the assumptions people make about what the people within Machu Picchu lived like. The physical evidence of the city is reliable, and defiantly useful but only to an extent.
0 notes